Is there a term for the belief that what is popular in society defines what is moral?











up vote
6
down vote

favorite
1












I have observed a number of people who believe, either explicitly or implicitly, that what is popular in a person’s society is what is moral. For instance, someone might say:




  • Polls say that 90% of Americans are in favor of X. Therefore, it’s morally permissible to do that.

  • Those who say Y is immoral are behind the times; the vast majority of society doesn’t believe that any more.

  • Everybody’s doing Z, so it must be okay


To be clear, the argument being made in these cases is that because something is popular, it is therefore moral (rather than popularity being a reflection of moral beliefs for other reasons).



I see this most commonly with sexual ethics (e.g. premarital sex, homosexuality, contraception), but occasionally for other things like intellectual property issues (e.g. pirating movies). A pretty typical way I see this is a reliance on opinion polls as justification for something being moral.



Is there a term for this explicit or implicit belief that what is popular in society defines what is moral?










share|improve this question






















  • Compare: social construct / social construction in sociology for a more underlying phenomena where popular norms are viewed as inherent
    – Samuel Russell
    Nov 25 at 1:45










  • Generational Normative Ethics? How a generation defines their own process of ethical behavior? So what is popular is current and what is moral is generational. Or maybe just Popular normative ethics.
    – Robus
    Nov 25 at 16:40

















up vote
6
down vote

favorite
1












I have observed a number of people who believe, either explicitly or implicitly, that what is popular in a person’s society is what is moral. For instance, someone might say:




  • Polls say that 90% of Americans are in favor of X. Therefore, it’s morally permissible to do that.

  • Those who say Y is immoral are behind the times; the vast majority of society doesn’t believe that any more.

  • Everybody’s doing Z, so it must be okay


To be clear, the argument being made in these cases is that because something is popular, it is therefore moral (rather than popularity being a reflection of moral beliefs for other reasons).



I see this most commonly with sexual ethics (e.g. premarital sex, homosexuality, contraception), but occasionally for other things like intellectual property issues (e.g. pirating movies). A pretty typical way I see this is a reliance on opinion polls as justification for something being moral.



Is there a term for this explicit or implicit belief that what is popular in society defines what is moral?










share|improve this question






















  • Compare: social construct / social construction in sociology for a more underlying phenomena where popular norms are viewed as inherent
    – Samuel Russell
    Nov 25 at 1:45










  • Generational Normative Ethics? How a generation defines their own process of ethical behavior? So what is popular is current and what is moral is generational. Or maybe just Popular normative ethics.
    – Robus
    Nov 25 at 16:40















up vote
6
down vote

favorite
1









up vote
6
down vote

favorite
1






1





I have observed a number of people who believe, either explicitly or implicitly, that what is popular in a person’s society is what is moral. For instance, someone might say:




  • Polls say that 90% of Americans are in favor of X. Therefore, it’s morally permissible to do that.

  • Those who say Y is immoral are behind the times; the vast majority of society doesn’t believe that any more.

  • Everybody’s doing Z, so it must be okay


To be clear, the argument being made in these cases is that because something is popular, it is therefore moral (rather than popularity being a reflection of moral beliefs for other reasons).



I see this most commonly with sexual ethics (e.g. premarital sex, homosexuality, contraception), but occasionally for other things like intellectual property issues (e.g. pirating movies). A pretty typical way I see this is a reliance on opinion polls as justification for something being moral.



Is there a term for this explicit or implicit belief that what is popular in society defines what is moral?










share|improve this question













I have observed a number of people who believe, either explicitly or implicitly, that what is popular in a person’s society is what is moral. For instance, someone might say:




  • Polls say that 90% of Americans are in favor of X. Therefore, it’s morally permissible to do that.

  • Those who say Y is immoral are behind the times; the vast majority of society doesn’t believe that any more.

  • Everybody’s doing Z, so it must be okay


To be clear, the argument being made in these cases is that because something is popular, it is therefore moral (rather than popularity being a reflection of moral beliefs for other reasons).



I see this most commonly with sexual ethics (e.g. premarital sex, homosexuality, contraception), but occasionally for other things like intellectual property issues (e.g. pirating movies). A pretty typical way I see this is a reliance on opinion polls as justification for something being moral.



Is there a term for this explicit or implicit belief that what is popular in society defines what is moral?







ethics terminology






share|improve this question













share|improve this question











share|improve this question




share|improve this question










asked Nov 24 at 16:07









Thunderforge

1377




1377












  • Compare: social construct / social construction in sociology for a more underlying phenomena where popular norms are viewed as inherent
    – Samuel Russell
    Nov 25 at 1:45










  • Generational Normative Ethics? How a generation defines their own process of ethical behavior? So what is popular is current and what is moral is generational. Or maybe just Popular normative ethics.
    – Robus
    Nov 25 at 16:40




















  • Compare: social construct / social construction in sociology for a more underlying phenomena where popular norms are viewed as inherent
    – Samuel Russell
    Nov 25 at 1:45










  • Generational Normative Ethics? How a generation defines their own process of ethical behavior? So what is popular is current and what is moral is generational. Or maybe just Popular normative ethics.
    – Robus
    Nov 25 at 16:40


















Compare: social construct / social construction in sociology for a more underlying phenomena where popular norms are viewed as inherent
– Samuel Russell
Nov 25 at 1:45




Compare: social construct / social construction in sociology for a more underlying phenomena where popular norms are viewed as inherent
– Samuel Russell
Nov 25 at 1:45












Generational Normative Ethics? How a generation defines their own process of ethical behavior? So what is popular is current and what is moral is generational. Or maybe just Popular normative ethics.
– Robus
Nov 25 at 16:40






Generational Normative Ethics? How a generation defines their own process of ethical behavior? So what is popular is current and what is moral is generational. Or maybe just Popular normative ethics.
– Robus
Nov 25 at 16:40












4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
9
down vote



accepted










My sense is that you are referring to a form of relativism that takes the specific form of morality by convention. Or at least that the social attitude you describe can be set out in these terms. It is capable of development beyond the banalities of prevailing forms of relativism. I develop this below, just slightly, but it may be that this is not at all your angle of interest. If it isn't, excuse the misunderstanding.



A version of this form of relativism can be found in FH Bradley's Ethical Studies, ch. V, 1876, in JN Findlay's 'Morality by Convention' (1944) and (at a stretch) in Wittgenstein's conception of 'forms of life' in Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958).



The central idea is that only in the context of a set of institutions, customs, and practices - a set of conventions - can moral obligations, duties, and rights arise. These institutions, customs, and practices are historically and socially specific; and since moral obligations, duties, and rights are indexed to them and vary with them, 'morality by convention', just described, is a form of relativism.



I am mainly trying to explain the idea of morality by convention, and not to defend it. But there is some substance to it. If you think of the morality of the English medieval manor, moral obligations, duties, and rights all stemmed from the institutions, customs, and practices of the time. The manorial rights of property-holding, for instance, were sustained by institutions, customs, and practices of the manor, and vanished when the social structure of the manor passed away.



An important point to note is that morality by convention is prescriptive, not merely descriptive. On this view of morality, moral obligations, duties, and rights are all actually binding - objectively binding. They are, if you care to put it so, emergent properties of the social structure. To outline them is not to do the sociology of morals, or merely to characterise popular morality. It is to specify real moral requirements, objectively binding on the community, but real moral requirements that are also relative to a specific social structure.



The oddity or distinctiveness of this idea - I use the terms neutrally - is not to be under-rated. We are all familiar with various forms of relativism, the burden of which is that there is no such thing as an objective morality - only moral diversity. Morality by convention takes us by surprise. It combines relativism and objectivity. On the other side, just as it interlocks relativism and objectivity, so also it breaks with the idea of a universal objective morality. Objective morality exists, all right, but in forms that are historically and socially specific and that need never converge in a single moral code.



Reading______________________________________________________________________



J.N. Findlay, 'Morality by Convention', Mind, Vol. 53, No. 210 (Apr., 1944), pp. 142-169.



F.H. Bradley, Ethical Studies, 1876 and regularly reprinted.



L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958), paras. 241-2 et passim. See further : https://nb.vse.cz/kfil/elogos/history/24_02_tonner.pdf.






share|improve this answer






























    up vote
    6
    down vote













    The system of morality being referred to is popular morality, and it is a current area of research in philosophy, with the following notable mentions:





    • Popular Morality and Unpopular Philosophy



      K. J. Dover maintains that the ancient Greeks recognized no rights other than those conferred by the laws of one's city. This chapter argues that examples from philosophy, history, and drama show that in certain cases Greeks regarded themselves as possessing rights independent of, and sometimes overriding the laws of the city. These rights were seen as grounded in divine law, in special obligations which individuals owed to the gods, or in nature.




    • Popular Morality, Custom, and Convention



      Unlike the classical world, ancient Israel has left little ‘popular’ literature, so reconstructing the moral codes of ordinary people is difficult. Nevertheless it is clear that some moral teachers—notably the prophets—met with resistance to their message, and from this we can form some idea of what was believed by people more generally, at least in some periods. There is some evidence of a conventional morality in Israel that does not derive from official sources, such as the Torah. In certain areas of moral thought, such as the ethics of war, there were conventions widely shared throughout the ancient Near East, and there must have been a popular morality for daily life, which sometimes emerges in biblical narratives.




    • Popular Morality in Herodotus



      This chapter states that the most debated area of 'popular morality' in Herodotus concerns its role in his analysis of the major decisions of the leading states and his complex categories of historical explanation. In his opening sentences Herodotus makes it clear that he sees it as his business to explain why major conflicts start, and to record how cities as well as individuals rise and fall, fall and rise, in changing patterns of human mutability. Herodotus is approving a moralizing judgment which explains the victory of the Greeks in terms of the imperialist aggression and blasphemy of their enemies. He offers the reader the hint that such moral and political contrasts are as subject to constant, yet unpredictable, change as are the prosperity or sufferings of individuals and the rise and fall of states.




    • Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle



      In ancient Greece, as today, popular moral attitudes differed importantly from the theories of moral philosophers. While for the latter we have Plato and Aristotle, this insightful work explores the everyday moral conceptions to which orators appealed in court and political assemblies, and which were reflected in non-philosophical literature. Oratory and comedy provide the primary testimony, and reference is also made to Sophocles, Euripides, Herodotus, Thucydides, Xenophon, and other sources. The selection of topics, the contrasts and comparisons with modern religious, social and legal principles, and accessibility to the non-specialist ensure the work's appeal to all readers with an interest in ancient Greek culture and social life.




    • Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire



      Morality is one of the fundamental structures of any society, enabling complex groups to form, negotiate their internal differences and persist through time. In the first book-length study of Roman popular morality, Dr Morgan argues that we can recover much of the moral thinking of people across the Empire. Her study draws on proverbs, fables, exemplary stories and gnomic quotations, to explore how morality worked as a system for Roman society as a whole and in individual lives. She examines the range of ideas and practices and their relative importance, as well as questions of authority and the relationship with high philosophy and the ethical vocabulary of documents and inscriptions. The Roman Empire incorporated numerous overlapping groups, whose ideas varied according to social status, geography, gender and many other factors. Nevertheless it could and did hold together as an ethical community, which was a significant factor in its socio-political success.




    • Magazine Humor and Popular Morality



      An example of popular morality in the modern era.




    We note that the term is mostly used in reference to moralities in ancient cultures, and appears less often in studies about modern culture.
    Studies like the latter prefer to use more specific terms such as "modern morality" or "modern moral philosophy" with the following examples:





    • Modern Moral Philosophy



      Although this collection of articles is not formally a commentary on Elizabeth Anscombe's famous article of the same title, in which she criticised the moral philosophy prevalent in 1958, a number of the contributors do take Anscombe's work as a starting point. Taken together the collection could be seen as a demonstration of the extent to which moral philosophers have since attempted to answer Anscombe's challenge, and to develop an approach to their subject which, while psychologically plausible, is neither based on divine law nor permissive of the impermissible.




    • Ancient Ethics and Modern Morality (a journal article)




    • Modern morality is just exhibitionism (a newspaper column)




    More popular and less academic articles tend to use the term "modern morality" in favour of "popular morality".






    share|improve this answer

















    • 1




      I don't think this really answers the OP's question. "Popular morality" refers to the moral views of the public (analogously to "popular culture"); the OP is asking about the belief that popular morality is dispositive.
      – ruakh
      Nov 25 at 5:03












    • @ruakh There are no terms to succintly describe beliefs in any doctrine without using the word "belief".
      – Carl Masens
      Nov 27 at 12:23










    • You are, of course, allowed to use the word "belief". :-)
      – ruakh
      Nov 27 at 16:00


















    up vote
    1
    down vote













    There must first be a distinction between moral, moral authority, popularity and ethics..



    Ethics and moral are pillar which hold a roof of truth where the popular view and perception should and ought to take shelter..
    Ethics define what is moraly acceptable per each population.. But that doesn't negate the fact that moral law is constant.. Eg) legalising abortion could be a popular vote in community X and unpopular in community Y.. But the fact remains,unethical to kill thus it it against moral law of life..
    So just because something passes the first law of popularity.. Is has to be passed though law 2 and 3 which more often than note are always constant..
    Referee
    Examples are neo-Aristotelians such as Hursthouse on abortion (1991) and on nature (2007), as well as neo-Kantians such as Regan on animals (1985), Korsgaard in general and in particular on animals and nature (1996), and Altman’s edited volume on the use and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy in applied ethics (2011).






    share|improve this answer



















    • 2




      I’m guessing you mean “moral” instead of “molar”? I don’t thnk you intended to talk about the ethics of teeth!
      – Thunderforge
      Nov 24 at 18:46








    • 1




      I agree with @Thunderforge that an edit should be made to fix the spelling. Welcome to this SE!
      – Frank Hubeny
      Nov 24 at 18:48










    • Tooth is the highest molar!
      – christo183
      Nov 26 at 12:55


















    up vote
    1
    down vote













    Are you possibly looking for a phrase like:
    Argumentum ad populum



    Loosely, this describes a rhetorical device (or fallacy, if considering debate in those terms) which seeks to use the popularity of an idea as implicit justification of the validity of the idea.






    share|improve this answer








    New contributor




    Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
    Check out our Code of Conduct.


















      Your Answer








      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "265"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      convertImagesToLinks: false,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: null,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f57401%2fis-there-a-term-for-the-belief-that-what-is-popular-in-society-defines-what-is-m%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      4 Answers
      4






      active

      oldest

      votes








      4 Answers
      4






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes








      up vote
      9
      down vote



      accepted










      My sense is that you are referring to a form of relativism that takes the specific form of morality by convention. Or at least that the social attitude you describe can be set out in these terms. It is capable of development beyond the banalities of prevailing forms of relativism. I develop this below, just slightly, but it may be that this is not at all your angle of interest. If it isn't, excuse the misunderstanding.



      A version of this form of relativism can be found in FH Bradley's Ethical Studies, ch. V, 1876, in JN Findlay's 'Morality by Convention' (1944) and (at a stretch) in Wittgenstein's conception of 'forms of life' in Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958).



      The central idea is that only in the context of a set of institutions, customs, and practices - a set of conventions - can moral obligations, duties, and rights arise. These institutions, customs, and practices are historically and socially specific; and since moral obligations, duties, and rights are indexed to them and vary with them, 'morality by convention', just described, is a form of relativism.



      I am mainly trying to explain the idea of morality by convention, and not to defend it. But there is some substance to it. If you think of the morality of the English medieval manor, moral obligations, duties, and rights all stemmed from the institutions, customs, and practices of the time. The manorial rights of property-holding, for instance, were sustained by institutions, customs, and practices of the manor, and vanished when the social structure of the manor passed away.



      An important point to note is that morality by convention is prescriptive, not merely descriptive. On this view of morality, moral obligations, duties, and rights are all actually binding - objectively binding. They are, if you care to put it so, emergent properties of the social structure. To outline them is not to do the sociology of morals, or merely to characterise popular morality. It is to specify real moral requirements, objectively binding on the community, but real moral requirements that are also relative to a specific social structure.



      The oddity or distinctiveness of this idea - I use the terms neutrally - is not to be under-rated. We are all familiar with various forms of relativism, the burden of which is that there is no such thing as an objective morality - only moral diversity. Morality by convention takes us by surprise. It combines relativism and objectivity. On the other side, just as it interlocks relativism and objectivity, so also it breaks with the idea of a universal objective morality. Objective morality exists, all right, but in forms that are historically and socially specific and that need never converge in a single moral code.



      Reading______________________________________________________________________



      J.N. Findlay, 'Morality by Convention', Mind, Vol. 53, No. 210 (Apr., 1944), pp. 142-169.



      F.H. Bradley, Ethical Studies, 1876 and regularly reprinted.



      L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958), paras. 241-2 et passim. See further : https://nb.vse.cz/kfil/elogos/history/24_02_tonner.pdf.






      share|improve this answer



























        up vote
        9
        down vote



        accepted










        My sense is that you are referring to a form of relativism that takes the specific form of morality by convention. Or at least that the social attitude you describe can be set out in these terms. It is capable of development beyond the banalities of prevailing forms of relativism. I develop this below, just slightly, but it may be that this is not at all your angle of interest. If it isn't, excuse the misunderstanding.



        A version of this form of relativism can be found in FH Bradley's Ethical Studies, ch. V, 1876, in JN Findlay's 'Morality by Convention' (1944) and (at a stretch) in Wittgenstein's conception of 'forms of life' in Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958).



        The central idea is that only in the context of a set of institutions, customs, and practices - a set of conventions - can moral obligations, duties, and rights arise. These institutions, customs, and practices are historically and socially specific; and since moral obligations, duties, and rights are indexed to them and vary with them, 'morality by convention', just described, is a form of relativism.



        I am mainly trying to explain the idea of morality by convention, and not to defend it. But there is some substance to it. If you think of the morality of the English medieval manor, moral obligations, duties, and rights all stemmed from the institutions, customs, and practices of the time. The manorial rights of property-holding, for instance, were sustained by institutions, customs, and practices of the manor, and vanished when the social structure of the manor passed away.



        An important point to note is that morality by convention is prescriptive, not merely descriptive. On this view of morality, moral obligations, duties, and rights are all actually binding - objectively binding. They are, if you care to put it so, emergent properties of the social structure. To outline them is not to do the sociology of morals, or merely to characterise popular morality. It is to specify real moral requirements, objectively binding on the community, but real moral requirements that are also relative to a specific social structure.



        The oddity or distinctiveness of this idea - I use the terms neutrally - is not to be under-rated. We are all familiar with various forms of relativism, the burden of which is that there is no such thing as an objective morality - only moral diversity. Morality by convention takes us by surprise. It combines relativism and objectivity. On the other side, just as it interlocks relativism and objectivity, so also it breaks with the idea of a universal objective morality. Objective morality exists, all right, but in forms that are historically and socially specific and that need never converge in a single moral code.



        Reading______________________________________________________________________



        J.N. Findlay, 'Morality by Convention', Mind, Vol. 53, No. 210 (Apr., 1944), pp. 142-169.



        F.H. Bradley, Ethical Studies, 1876 and regularly reprinted.



        L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958), paras. 241-2 et passim. See further : https://nb.vse.cz/kfil/elogos/history/24_02_tonner.pdf.






        share|improve this answer

























          up vote
          9
          down vote



          accepted







          up vote
          9
          down vote



          accepted






          My sense is that you are referring to a form of relativism that takes the specific form of morality by convention. Or at least that the social attitude you describe can be set out in these terms. It is capable of development beyond the banalities of prevailing forms of relativism. I develop this below, just slightly, but it may be that this is not at all your angle of interest. If it isn't, excuse the misunderstanding.



          A version of this form of relativism can be found in FH Bradley's Ethical Studies, ch. V, 1876, in JN Findlay's 'Morality by Convention' (1944) and (at a stretch) in Wittgenstein's conception of 'forms of life' in Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958).



          The central idea is that only in the context of a set of institutions, customs, and practices - a set of conventions - can moral obligations, duties, and rights arise. These institutions, customs, and practices are historically and socially specific; and since moral obligations, duties, and rights are indexed to them and vary with them, 'morality by convention', just described, is a form of relativism.



          I am mainly trying to explain the idea of morality by convention, and not to defend it. But there is some substance to it. If you think of the morality of the English medieval manor, moral obligations, duties, and rights all stemmed from the institutions, customs, and practices of the time. The manorial rights of property-holding, for instance, were sustained by institutions, customs, and practices of the manor, and vanished when the social structure of the manor passed away.



          An important point to note is that morality by convention is prescriptive, not merely descriptive. On this view of morality, moral obligations, duties, and rights are all actually binding - objectively binding. They are, if you care to put it so, emergent properties of the social structure. To outline them is not to do the sociology of morals, or merely to characterise popular morality. It is to specify real moral requirements, objectively binding on the community, but real moral requirements that are also relative to a specific social structure.



          The oddity or distinctiveness of this idea - I use the terms neutrally - is not to be under-rated. We are all familiar with various forms of relativism, the burden of which is that there is no such thing as an objective morality - only moral diversity. Morality by convention takes us by surprise. It combines relativism and objectivity. On the other side, just as it interlocks relativism and objectivity, so also it breaks with the idea of a universal objective morality. Objective morality exists, all right, but in forms that are historically and socially specific and that need never converge in a single moral code.



          Reading______________________________________________________________________



          J.N. Findlay, 'Morality by Convention', Mind, Vol. 53, No. 210 (Apr., 1944), pp. 142-169.



          F.H. Bradley, Ethical Studies, 1876 and regularly reprinted.



          L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958), paras. 241-2 et passim. See further : https://nb.vse.cz/kfil/elogos/history/24_02_tonner.pdf.






          share|improve this answer














          My sense is that you are referring to a form of relativism that takes the specific form of morality by convention. Or at least that the social attitude you describe can be set out in these terms. It is capable of development beyond the banalities of prevailing forms of relativism. I develop this below, just slightly, but it may be that this is not at all your angle of interest. If it isn't, excuse the misunderstanding.



          A version of this form of relativism can be found in FH Bradley's Ethical Studies, ch. V, 1876, in JN Findlay's 'Morality by Convention' (1944) and (at a stretch) in Wittgenstein's conception of 'forms of life' in Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958).



          The central idea is that only in the context of a set of institutions, customs, and practices - a set of conventions - can moral obligations, duties, and rights arise. These institutions, customs, and practices are historically and socially specific; and since moral obligations, duties, and rights are indexed to them and vary with them, 'morality by convention', just described, is a form of relativism.



          I am mainly trying to explain the idea of morality by convention, and not to defend it. But there is some substance to it. If you think of the morality of the English medieval manor, moral obligations, duties, and rights all stemmed from the institutions, customs, and practices of the time. The manorial rights of property-holding, for instance, were sustained by institutions, customs, and practices of the manor, and vanished when the social structure of the manor passed away.



          An important point to note is that morality by convention is prescriptive, not merely descriptive. On this view of morality, moral obligations, duties, and rights are all actually binding - objectively binding. They are, if you care to put it so, emergent properties of the social structure. To outline them is not to do the sociology of morals, or merely to characterise popular morality. It is to specify real moral requirements, objectively binding on the community, but real moral requirements that are also relative to a specific social structure.



          The oddity or distinctiveness of this idea - I use the terms neutrally - is not to be under-rated. We are all familiar with various forms of relativism, the burden of which is that there is no such thing as an objective morality - only moral diversity. Morality by convention takes us by surprise. It combines relativism and objectivity. On the other side, just as it interlocks relativism and objectivity, so also it breaks with the idea of a universal objective morality. Objective morality exists, all right, but in forms that are historically and socially specific and that need never converge in a single moral code.



          Reading______________________________________________________________________



          J.N. Findlay, 'Morality by Convention', Mind, Vol. 53, No. 210 (Apr., 1944), pp. 142-169.



          F.H. Bradley, Ethical Studies, 1876 and regularly reprinted.



          L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (1953, rev. 1958), paras. 241-2 et passim. See further : https://nb.vse.cz/kfil/elogos/history/24_02_tonner.pdf.







          share|improve this answer














          share|improve this answer



          share|improve this answer








          edited Nov 25 at 11:50

























          answered Nov 24 at 18:30









          Geoffrey Thomas

          22.1k22088




          22.1k22088






















              up vote
              6
              down vote













              The system of morality being referred to is popular morality, and it is a current area of research in philosophy, with the following notable mentions:





              • Popular Morality and Unpopular Philosophy



                K. J. Dover maintains that the ancient Greeks recognized no rights other than those conferred by the laws of one's city. This chapter argues that examples from philosophy, history, and drama show that in certain cases Greeks regarded themselves as possessing rights independent of, and sometimes overriding the laws of the city. These rights were seen as grounded in divine law, in special obligations which individuals owed to the gods, or in nature.




              • Popular Morality, Custom, and Convention



                Unlike the classical world, ancient Israel has left little ‘popular’ literature, so reconstructing the moral codes of ordinary people is difficult. Nevertheless it is clear that some moral teachers—notably the prophets—met with resistance to their message, and from this we can form some idea of what was believed by people more generally, at least in some periods. There is some evidence of a conventional morality in Israel that does not derive from official sources, such as the Torah. In certain areas of moral thought, such as the ethics of war, there were conventions widely shared throughout the ancient Near East, and there must have been a popular morality for daily life, which sometimes emerges in biblical narratives.




              • Popular Morality in Herodotus



                This chapter states that the most debated area of 'popular morality' in Herodotus concerns its role in his analysis of the major decisions of the leading states and his complex categories of historical explanation. In his opening sentences Herodotus makes it clear that he sees it as his business to explain why major conflicts start, and to record how cities as well as individuals rise and fall, fall and rise, in changing patterns of human mutability. Herodotus is approving a moralizing judgment which explains the victory of the Greeks in terms of the imperialist aggression and blasphemy of their enemies. He offers the reader the hint that such moral and political contrasts are as subject to constant, yet unpredictable, change as are the prosperity or sufferings of individuals and the rise and fall of states.




              • Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle



                In ancient Greece, as today, popular moral attitudes differed importantly from the theories of moral philosophers. While for the latter we have Plato and Aristotle, this insightful work explores the everyday moral conceptions to which orators appealed in court and political assemblies, and which were reflected in non-philosophical literature. Oratory and comedy provide the primary testimony, and reference is also made to Sophocles, Euripides, Herodotus, Thucydides, Xenophon, and other sources. The selection of topics, the contrasts and comparisons with modern religious, social and legal principles, and accessibility to the non-specialist ensure the work's appeal to all readers with an interest in ancient Greek culture and social life.




              • Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire



                Morality is one of the fundamental structures of any society, enabling complex groups to form, negotiate their internal differences and persist through time. In the first book-length study of Roman popular morality, Dr Morgan argues that we can recover much of the moral thinking of people across the Empire. Her study draws on proverbs, fables, exemplary stories and gnomic quotations, to explore how morality worked as a system for Roman society as a whole and in individual lives. She examines the range of ideas and practices and their relative importance, as well as questions of authority and the relationship with high philosophy and the ethical vocabulary of documents and inscriptions. The Roman Empire incorporated numerous overlapping groups, whose ideas varied according to social status, geography, gender and many other factors. Nevertheless it could and did hold together as an ethical community, which was a significant factor in its socio-political success.




              • Magazine Humor and Popular Morality



                An example of popular morality in the modern era.




              We note that the term is mostly used in reference to moralities in ancient cultures, and appears less often in studies about modern culture.
              Studies like the latter prefer to use more specific terms such as "modern morality" or "modern moral philosophy" with the following examples:





              • Modern Moral Philosophy



                Although this collection of articles is not formally a commentary on Elizabeth Anscombe's famous article of the same title, in which she criticised the moral philosophy prevalent in 1958, a number of the contributors do take Anscombe's work as a starting point. Taken together the collection could be seen as a demonstration of the extent to which moral philosophers have since attempted to answer Anscombe's challenge, and to develop an approach to their subject which, while psychologically plausible, is neither based on divine law nor permissive of the impermissible.




              • Ancient Ethics and Modern Morality (a journal article)




              • Modern morality is just exhibitionism (a newspaper column)




              More popular and less academic articles tend to use the term "modern morality" in favour of "popular morality".






              share|improve this answer

















              • 1




                I don't think this really answers the OP's question. "Popular morality" refers to the moral views of the public (analogously to "popular culture"); the OP is asking about the belief that popular morality is dispositive.
                – ruakh
                Nov 25 at 5:03












              • @ruakh There are no terms to succintly describe beliefs in any doctrine without using the word "belief".
                – Carl Masens
                Nov 27 at 12:23










              • You are, of course, allowed to use the word "belief". :-)
                – ruakh
                Nov 27 at 16:00















              up vote
              6
              down vote













              The system of morality being referred to is popular morality, and it is a current area of research in philosophy, with the following notable mentions:





              • Popular Morality and Unpopular Philosophy



                K. J. Dover maintains that the ancient Greeks recognized no rights other than those conferred by the laws of one's city. This chapter argues that examples from philosophy, history, and drama show that in certain cases Greeks regarded themselves as possessing rights independent of, and sometimes overriding the laws of the city. These rights were seen as grounded in divine law, in special obligations which individuals owed to the gods, or in nature.




              • Popular Morality, Custom, and Convention



                Unlike the classical world, ancient Israel has left little ‘popular’ literature, so reconstructing the moral codes of ordinary people is difficult. Nevertheless it is clear that some moral teachers—notably the prophets—met with resistance to their message, and from this we can form some idea of what was believed by people more generally, at least in some periods. There is some evidence of a conventional morality in Israel that does not derive from official sources, such as the Torah. In certain areas of moral thought, such as the ethics of war, there were conventions widely shared throughout the ancient Near East, and there must have been a popular morality for daily life, which sometimes emerges in biblical narratives.




              • Popular Morality in Herodotus



                This chapter states that the most debated area of 'popular morality' in Herodotus concerns its role in his analysis of the major decisions of the leading states and his complex categories of historical explanation. In his opening sentences Herodotus makes it clear that he sees it as his business to explain why major conflicts start, and to record how cities as well as individuals rise and fall, fall and rise, in changing patterns of human mutability. Herodotus is approving a moralizing judgment which explains the victory of the Greeks in terms of the imperialist aggression and blasphemy of their enemies. He offers the reader the hint that such moral and political contrasts are as subject to constant, yet unpredictable, change as are the prosperity or sufferings of individuals and the rise and fall of states.




              • Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle



                In ancient Greece, as today, popular moral attitudes differed importantly from the theories of moral philosophers. While for the latter we have Plato and Aristotle, this insightful work explores the everyday moral conceptions to which orators appealed in court and political assemblies, and which were reflected in non-philosophical literature. Oratory and comedy provide the primary testimony, and reference is also made to Sophocles, Euripides, Herodotus, Thucydides, Xenophon, and other sources. The selection of topics, the contrasts and comparisons with modern religious, social and legal principles, and accessibility to the non-specialist ensure the work's appeal to all readers with an interest in ancient Greek culture and social life.




              • Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire



                Morality is one of the fundamental structures of any society, enabling complex groups to form, negotiate their internal differences and persist through time. In the first book-length study of Roman popular morality, Dr Morgan argues that we can recover much of the moral thinking of people across the Empire. Her study draws on proverbs, fables, exemplary stories and gnomic quotations, to explore how morality worked as a system for Roman society as a whole and in individual lives. She examines the range of ideas and practices and their relative importance, as well as questions of authority and the relationship with high philosophy and the ethical vocabulary of documents and inscriptions. The Roman Empire incorporated numerous overlapping groups, whose ideas varied according to social status, geography, gender and many other factors. Nevertheless it could and did hold together as an ethical community, which was a significant factor in its socio-political success.




              • Magazine Humor and Popular Morality



                An example of popular morality in the modern era.




              We note that the term is mostly used in reference to moralities in ancient cultures, and appears less often in studies about modern culture.
              Studies like the latter prefer to use more specific terms such as "modern morality" or "modern moral philosophy" with the following examples:





              • Modern Moral Philosophy



                Although this collection of articles is not formally a commentary on Elizabeth Anscombe's famous article of the same title, in which she criticised the moral philosophy prevalent in 1958, a number of the contributors do take Anscombe's work as a starting point. Taken together the collection could be seen as a demonstration of the extent to which moral philosophers have since attempted to answer Anscombe's challenge, and to develop an approach to their subject which, while psychologically plausible, is neither based on divine law nor permissive of the impermissible.




              • Ancient Ethics and Modern Morality (a journal article)




              • Modern morality is just exhibitionism (a newspaper column)




              More popular and less academic articles tend to use the term "modern morality" in favour of "popular morality".






              share|improve this answer

















              • 1




                I don't think this really answers the OP's question. "Popular morality" refers to the moral views of the public (analogously to "popular culture"); the OP is asking about the belief that popular morality is dispositive.
                – ruakh
                Nov 25 at 5:03












              • @ruakh There are no terms to succintly describe beliefs in any doctrine without using the word "belief".
                – Carl Masens
                Nov 27 at 12:23










              • You are, of course, allowed to use the word "belief". :-)
                – ruakh
                Nov 27 at 16:00













              up vote
              6
              down vote










              up vote
              6
              down vote









              The system of morality being referred to is popular morality, and it is a current area of research in philosophy, with the following notable mentions:





              • Popular Morality and Unpopular Philosophy



                K. J. Dover maintains that the ancient Greeks recognized no rights other than those conferred by the laws of one's city. This chapter argues that examples from philosophy, history, and drama show that in certain cases Greeks regarded themselves as possessing rights independent of, and sometimes overriding the laws of the city. These rights were seen as grounded in divine law, in special obligations which individuals owed to the gods, or in nature.




              • Popular Morality, Custom, and Convention



                Unlike the classical world, ancient Israel has left little ‘popular’ literature, so reconstructing the moral codes of ordinary people is difficult. Nevertheless it is clear that some moral teachers—notably the prophets—met with resistance to their message, and from this we can form some idea of what was believed by people more generally, at least in some periods. There is some evidence of a conventional morality in Israel that does not derive from official sources, such as the Torah. In certain areas of moral thought, such as the ethics of war, there were conventions widely shared throughout the ancient Near East, and there must have been a popular morality for daily life, which sometimes emerges in biblical narratives.




              • Popular Morality in Herodotus



                This chapter states that the most debated area of 'popular morality' in Herodotus concerns its role in his analysis of the major decisions of the leading states and his complex categories of historical explanation. In his opening sentences Herodotus makes it clear that he sees it as his business to explain why major conflicts start, and to record how cities as well as individuals rise and fall, fall and rise, in changing patterns of human mutability. Herodotus is approving a moralizing judgment which explains the victory of the Greeks in terms of the imperialist aggression and blasphemy of their enemies. He offers the reader the hint that such moral and political contrasts are as subject to constant, yet unpredictable, change as are the prosperity or sufferings of individuals and the rise and fall of states.




              • Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle



                In ancient Greece, as today, popular moral attitudes differed importantly from the theories of moral philosophers. While for the latter we have Plato and Aristotle, this insightful work explores the everyday moral conceptions to which orators appealed in court and political assemblies, and which were reflected in non-philosophical literature. Oratory and comedy provide the primary testimony, and reference is also made to Sophocles, Euripides, Herodotus, Thucydides, Xenophon, and other sources. The selection of topics, the contrasts and comparisons with modern religious, social and legal principles, and accessibility to the non-specialist ensure the work's appeal to all readers with an interest in ancient Greek culture and social life.




              • Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire



                Morality is one of the fundamental structures of any society, enabling complex groups to form, negotiate their internal differences and persist through time. In the first book-length study of Roman popular morality, Dr Morgan argues that we can recover much of the moral thinking of people across the Empire. Her study draws on proverbs, fables, exemplary stories and gnomic quotations, to explore how morality worked as a system for Roman society as a whole and in individual lives. She examines the range of ideas and practices and their relative importance, as well as questions of authority and the relationship with high philosophy and the ethical vocabulary of documents and inscriptions. The Roman Empire incorporated numerous overlapping groups, whose ideas varied according to social status, geography, gender and many other factors. Nevertheless it could and did hold together as an ethical community, which was a significant factor in its socio-political success.




              • Magazine Humor and Popular Morality



                An example of popular morality in the modern era.




              We note that the term is mostly used in reference to moralities in ancient cultures, and appears less often in studies about modern culture.
              Studies like the latter prefer to use more specific terms such as "modern morality" or "modern moral philosophy" with the following examples:





              • Modern Moral Philosophy



                Although this collection of articles is not formally a commentary on Elizabeth Anscombe's famous article of the same title, in which she criticised the moral philosophy prevalent in 1958, a number of the contributors do take Anscombe's work as a starting point. Taken together the collection could be seen as a demonstration of the extent to which moral philosophers have since attempted to answer Anscombe's challenge, and to develop an approach to their subject which, while psychologically plausible, is neither based on divine law nor permissive of the impermissible.




              • Ancient Ethics and Modern Morality (a journal article)




              • Modern morality is just exhibitionism (a newspaper column)




              More popular and less academic articles tend to use the term "modern morality" in favour of "popular morality".






              share|improve this answer












              The system of morality being referred to is popular morality, and it is a current area of research in philosophy, with the following notable mentions:





              • Popular Morality and Unpopular Philosophy



                K. J. Dover maintains that the ancient Greeks recognized no rights other than those conferred by the laws of one's city. This chapter argues that examples from philosophy, history, and drama show that in certain cases Greeks regarded themselves as possessing rights independent of, and sometimes overriding the laws of the city. These rights were seen as grounded in divine law, in special obligations which individuals owed to the gods, or in nature.




              • Popular Morality, Custom, and Convention



                Unlike the classical world, ancient Israel has left little ‘popular’ literature, so reconstructing the moral codes of ordinary people is difficult. Nevertheless it is clear that some moral teachers—notably the prophets—met with resistance to their message, and from this we can form some idea of what was believed by people more generally, at least in some periods. There is some evidence of a conventional morality in Israel that does not derive from official sources, such as the Torah. In certain areas of moral thought, such as the ethics of war, there were conventions widely shared throughout the ancient Near East, and there must have been a popular morality for daily life, which sometimes emerges in biblical narratives.




              • Popular Morality in Herodotus



                This chapter states that the most debated area of 'popular morality' in Herodotus concerns its role in his analysis of the major decisions of the leading states and his complex categories of historical explanation. In his opening sentences Herodotus makes it clear that he sees it as his business to explain why major conflicts start, and to record how cities as well as individuals rise and fall, fall and rise, in changing patterns of human mutability. Herodotus is approving a moralizing judgment which explains the victory of the Greeks in terms of the imperialist aggression and blasphemy of their enemies. He offers the reader the hint that such moral and political contrasts are as subject to constant, yet unpredictable, change as are the prosperity or sufferings of individuals and the rise and fall of states.




              • Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle



                In ancient Greece, as today, popular moral attitudes differed importantly from the theories of moral philosophers. While for the latter we have Plato and Aristotle, this insightful work explores the everyday moral conceptions to which orators appealed in court and political assemblies, and which were reflected in non-philosophical literature. Oratory and comedy provide the primary testimony, and reference is also made to Sophocles, Euripides, Herodotus, Thucydides, Xenophon, and other sources. The selection of topics, the contrasts and comparisons with modern religious, social and legal principles, and accessibility to the non-specialist ensure the work's appeal to all readers with an interest in ancient Greek culture and social life.




              • Popular Morality in the Early Roman Empire



                Morality is one of the fundamental structures of any society, enabling complex groups to form, negotiate their internal differences and persist through time. In the first book-length study of Roman popular morality, Dr Morgan argues that we can recover much of the moral thinking of people across the Empire. Her study draws on proverbs, fables, exemplary stories and gnomic quotations, to explore how morality worked as a system for Roman society as a whole and in individual lives. She examines the range of ideas and practices and their relative importance, as well as questions of authority and the relationship with high philosophy and the ethical vocabulary of documents and inscriptions. The Roman Empire incorporated numerous overlapping groups, whose ideas varied according to social status, geography, gender and many other factors. Nevertheless it could and did hold together as an ethical community, which was a significant factor in its socio-political success.




              • Magazine Humor and Popular Morality



                An example of popular morality in the modern era.




              We note that the term is mostly used in reference to moralities in ancient cultures, and appears less often in studies about modern culture.
              Studies like the latter prefer to use more specific terms such as "modern morality" or "modern moral philosophy" with the following examples:





              • Modern Moral Philosophy



                Although this collection of articles is not formally a commentary on Elizabeth Anscombe's famous article of the same title, in which she criticised the moral philosophy prevalent in 1958, a number of the contributors do take Anscombe's work as a starting point. Taken together the collection could be seen as a demonstration of the extent to which moral philosophers have since attempted to answer Anscombe's challenge, and to develop an approach to their subject which, while psychologically plausible, is neither based on divine law nor permissive of the impermissible.




              • Ancient Ethics and Modern Morality (a journal article)




              • Modern morality is just exhibitionism (a newspaper column)




              More popular and less academic articles tend to use the term "modern morality" in favour of "popular morality".







              share|improve this answer












              share|improve this answer



              share|improve this answer










              answered Nov 24 at 16:28









              Carl Masens

              41719




              41719








              • 1




                I don't think this really answers the OP's question. "Popular morality" refers to the moral views of the public (analogously to "popular culture"); the OP is asking about the belief that popular morality is dispositive.
                – ruakh
                Nov 25 at 5:03












              • @ruakh There are no terms to succintly describe beliefs in any doctrine without using the word "belief".
                – Carl Masens
                Nov 27 at 12:23










              • You are, of course, allowed to use the word "belief". :-)
                – ruakh
                Nov 27 at 16:00














              • 1




                I don't think this really answers the OP's question. "Popular morality" refers to the moral views of the public (analogously to "popular culture"); the OP is asking about the belief that popular morality is dispositive.
                – ruakh
                Nov 25 at 5:03












              • @ruakh There are no terms to succintly describe beliefs in any doctrine without using the word "belief".
                – Carl Masens
                Nov 27 at 12:23










              • You are, of course, allowed to use the word "belief". :-)
                – ruakh
                Nov 27 at 16:00








              1




              1




              I don't think this really answers the OP's question. "Popular morality" refers to the moral views of the public (analogously to "popular culture"); the OP is asking about the belief that popular morality is dispositive.
              – ruakh
              Nov 25 at 5:03






              I don't think this really answers the OP's question. "Popular morality" refers to the moral views of the public (analogously to "popular culture"); the OP is asking about the belief that popular morality is dispositive.
              – ruakh
              Nov 25 at 5:03














              @ruakh There are no terms to succintly describe beliefs in any doctrine without using the word "belief".
              – Carl Masens
              Nov 27 at 12:23




              @ruakh There are no terms to succintly describe beliefs in any doctrine without using the word "belief".
              – Carl Masens
              Nov 27 at 12:23












              You are, of course, allowed to use the word "belief". :-)
              – ruakh
              Nov 27 at 16:00




              You are, of course, allowed to use the word "belief". :-)
              – ruakh
              Nov 27 at 16:00










              up vote
              1
              down vote













              There must first be a distinction between moral, moral authority, popularity and ethics..



              Ethics and moral are pillar which hold a roof of truth where the popular view and perception should and ought to take shelter..
              Ethics define what is moraly acceptable per each population.. But that doesn't negate the fact that moral law is constant.. Eg) legalising abortion could be a popular vote in community X and unpopular in community Y.. But the fact remains,unethical to kill thus it it against moral law of life..
              So just because something passes the first law of popularity.. Is has to be passed though law 2 and 3 which more often than note are always constant..
              Referee
              Examples are neo-Aristotelians such as Hursthouse on abortion (1991) and on nature (2007), as well as neo-Kantians such as Regan on animals (1985), Korsgaard in general and in particular on animals and nature (1996), and Altman’s edited volume on the use and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy in applied ethics (2011).






              share|improve this answer



















              • 2




                I’m guessing you mean “moral” instead of “molar”? I don’t thnk you intended to talk about the ethics of teeth!
                – Thunderforge
                Nov 24 at 18:46








              • 1




                I agree with @Thunderforge that an edit should be made to fix the spelling. Welcome to this SE!
                – Frank Hubeny
                Nov 24 at 18:48










              • Tooth is the highest molar!
                – christo183
                Nov 26 at 12:55















              up vote
              1
              down vote













              There must first be a distinction between moral, moral authority, popularity and ethics..



              Ethics and moral are pillar which hold a roof of truth where the popular view and perception should and ought to take shelter..
              Ethics define what is moraly acceptable per each population.. But that doesn't negate the fact that moral law is constant.. Eg) legalising abortion could be a popular vote in community X and unpopular in community Y.. But the fact remains,unethical to kill thus it it against moral law of life..
              So just because something passes the first law of popularity.. Is has to be passed though law 2 and 3 which more often than note are always constant..
              Referee
              Examples are neo-Aristotelians such as Hursthouse on abortion (1991) and on nature (2007), as well as neo-Kantians such as Regan on animals (1985), Korsgaard in general and in particular on animals and nature (1996), and Altman’s edited volume on the use and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy in applied ethics (2011).






              share|improve this answer



















              • 2




                I’m guessing you mean “moral” instead of “molar”? I don’t thnk you intended to talk about the ethics of teeth!
                – Thunderforge
                Nov 24 at 18:46








              • 1




                I agree with @Thunderforge that an edit should be made to fix the spelling. Welcome to this SE!
                – Frank Hubeny
                Nov 24 at 18:48










              • Tooth is the highest molar!
                – christo183
                Nov 26 at 12:55













              up vote
              1
              down vote










              up vote
              1
              down vote









              There must first be a distinction between moral, moral authority, popularity and ethics..



              Ethics and moral are pillar which hold a roof of truth where the popular view and perception should and ought to take shelter..
              Ethics define what is moraly acceptable per each population.. But that doesn't negate the fact that moral law is constant.. Eg) legalising abortion could be a popular vote in community X and unpopular in community Y.. But the fact remains,unethical to kill thus it it against moral law of life..
              So just because something passes the first law of popularity.. Is has to be passed though law 2 and 3 which more often than note are always constant..
              Referee
              Examples are neo-Aristotelians such as Hursthouse on abortion (1991) and on nature (2007), as well as neo-Kantians such as Regan on animals (1985), Korsgaard in general and in particular on animals and nature (1996), and Altman’s edited volume on the use and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy in applied ethics (2011).






              share|improve this answer














              There must first be a distinction between moral, moral authority, popularity and ethics..



              Ethics and moral are pillar which hold a roof of truth where the popular view and perception should and ought to take shelter..
              Ethics define what is moraly acceptable per each population.. But that doesn't negate the fact that moral law is constant.. Eg) legalising abortion could be a popular vote in community X and unpopular in community Y.. But the fact remains,unethical to kill thus it it against moral law of life..
              So just because something passes the first law of popularity.. Is has to be passed though law 2 and 3 which more often than note are always constant..
              Referee
              Examples are neo-Aristotelians such as Hursthouse on abortion (1991) and on nature (2007), as well as neo-Kantians such as Regan on animals (1985), Korsgaard in general and in particular on animals and nature (1996), and Altman’s edited volume on the use and limits of Kant’s practical philosophy in applied ethics (2011).







              share|improve this answer














              share|improve this answer



              share|improve this answer








              edited Nov 25 at 8:34









              RonJohn

              1334




              1334










              answered Nov 24 at 18:38









              J. Gaithuma

              112




              112








              • 2




                I’m guessing you mean “moral” instead of “molar”? I don’t thnk you intended to talk about the ethics of teeth!
                – Thunderforge
                Nov 24 at 18:46








              • 1




                I agree with @Thunderforge that an edit should be made to fix the spelling. Welcome to this SE!
                – Frank Hubeny
                Nov 24 at 18:48










              • Tooth is the highest molar!
                – christo183
                Nov 26 at 12:55














              • 2




                I’m guessing you mean “moral” instead of “molar”? I don’t thnk you intended to talk about the ethics of teeth!
                – Thunderforge
                Nov 24 at 18:46








              • 1




                I agree with @Thunderforge that an edit should be made to fix the spelling. Welcome to this SE!
                – Frank Hubeny
                Nov 24 at 18:48










              • Tooth is the highest molar!
                – christo183
                Nov 26 at 12:55








              2




              2




              I’m guessing you mean “moral” instead of “molar”? I don’t thnk you intended to talk about the ethics of teeth!
              – Thunderforge
              Nov 24 at 18:46






              I’m guessing you mean “moral” instead of “molar”? I don’t thnk you intended to talk about the ethics of teeth!
              – Thunderforge
              Nov 24 at 18:46






              1




              1




              I agree with @Thunderforge that an edit should be made to fix the spelling. Welcome to this SE!
              – Frank Hubeny
              Nov 24 at 18:48




              I agree with @Thunderforge that an edit should be made to fix the spelling. Welcome to this SE!
              – Frank Hubeny
              Nov 24 at 18:48












              Tooth is the highest molar!
              – christo183
              Nov 26 at 12:55




              Tooth is the highest molar!
              – christo183
              Nov 26 at 12:55










              up vote
              1
              down vote













              Are you possibly looking for a phrase like:
              Argumentum ad populum



              Loosely, this describes a rhetorical device (or fallacy, if considering debate in those terms) which seeks to use the popularity of an idea as implicit justification of the validity of the idea.






              share|improve this answer








              New contributor




              Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
              Check out our Code of Conduct.






















                up vote
                1
                down vote













                Are you possibly looking for a phrase like:
                Argumentum ad populum



                Loosely, this describes a rhetorical device (or fallacy, if considering debate in those terms) which seeks to use the popularity of an idea as implicit justification of the validity of the idea.






                share|improve this answer








                New contributor




                Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                Check out our Code of Conduct.




















                  up vote
                  1
                  down vote










                  up vote
                  1
                  down vote









                  Are you possibly looking for a phrase like:
                  Argumentum ad populum



                  Loosely, this describes a rhetorical device (or fallacy, if considering debate in those terms) which seeks to use the popularity of an idea as implicit justification of the validity of the idea.






                  share|improve this answer








                  New contributor




                  Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.









                  Are you possibly looking for a phrase like:
                  Argumentum ad populum



                  Loosely, this describes a rhetorical device (or fallacy, if considering debate in those terms) which seeks to use the popularity of an idea as implicit justification of the validity of the idea.







                  share|improve this answer








                  New contributor




                  Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.









                  share|improve this answer



                  share|improve this answer






                  New contributor




                  Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.









                  answered Nov 25 at 11:12









                  Zac

                  112




                  112




                  New contributor




                  Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.





                  New contributor





                  Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.






                  Zac is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
                  Check out our Code of Conduct.






























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Philosophy Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





                      Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


                      Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f57401%2fis-there-a-term-for-the-belief-that-what-is-popular-in-society-defines-what-is-m%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      If I really need a card on my start hand, how many mulligans make sense? [duplicate]

                      Alcedinidae

                      Can an atomic nucleus contain both particles and antiparticles? [duplicate]