Difficulty with understanding the semantics of the following equivalences











up vote
6
down vote

favorite
1












I know that the rules for removing quantifiers from the antecedent of a conditional are as follows:
(∀x)φ(x) → ψ ⇔ (∃x)(φ(x) → ψ) and (∃x)φ(x) → ψ ⇔ (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ), provided that x is not free in ψ.
I also know that the rules for removing quantifiers from the consequent are as follows:
φ → (∀x)ψ(x) ⇔ (∀x)(φ → ψ(x)) and φ → (∃x)ψ(x) ⇔ (∃x)(φ → ψ(x)), provided that x is not free in φ.



Now, I understand how to derive these equivalences syntactically. However, I can't seem to grasp how the first two can be semantically equivalent.

For example, how can two sentences such as "If all x are wet, then it's raining" and "There exists an x such that if x is wet, then it's raining" can be equivalent?

Moreover, provided that x is not free in ψ, isn't (∀x)φ(x) → ψ equivalent to (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ)? Which would result in the absurd equivalence: (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ) ⇔ (∃x)(φ(x) → ψ).



I think that my difficulty here arises from a misunderstanding of the significance of the parentheses in the aforementioned equivalences. Please provide examples in your answer if you can.










share|improve this question









New contributor




Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.
























    up vote
    6
    down vote

    favorite
    1












    I know that the rules for removing quantifiers from the antecedent of a conditional are as follows:
    (∀x)φ(x) → ψ ⇔ (∃x)(φ(x) → ψ) and (∃x)φ(x) → ψ ⇔ (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ), provided that x is not free in ψ.
    I also know that the rules for removing quantifiers from the consequent are as follows:
    φ → (∀x)ψ(x) ⇔ (∀x)(φ → ψ(x)) and φ → (∃x)ψ(x) ⇔ (∃x)(φ → ψ(x)), provided that x is not free in φ.



    Now, I understand how to derive these equivalences syntactically. However, I can't seem to grasp how the first two can be semantically equivalent.

    For example, how can two sentences such as "If all x are wet, then it's raining" and "There exists an x such that if x is wet, then it's raining" can be equivalent?

    Moreover, provided that x is not free in ψ, isn't (∀x)φ(x) → ψ equivalent to (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ)? Which would result in the absurd equivalence: (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ) ⇔ (∃x)(φ(x) → ψ).



    I think that my difficulty here arises from a misunderstanding of the significance of the parentheses in the aforementioned equivalences. Please provide examples in your answer if you can.










    share|improve this question









    New contributor




    Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
    Check out our Code of Conduct.






















      up vote
      6
      down vote

      favorite
      1









      up vote
      6
      down vote

      favorite
      1






      1





      I know that the rules for removing quantifiers from the antecedent of a conditional are as follows:
      (∀x)φ(x) → ψ ⇔ (∃x)(φ(x) → ψ) and (∃x)φ(x) → ψ ⇔ (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ), provided that x is not free in ψ.
      I also know that the rules for removing quantifiers from the consequent are as follows:
      φ → (∀x)ψ(x) ⇔ (∀x)(φ → ψ(x)) and φ → (∃x)ψ(x) ⇔ (∃x)(φ → ψ(x)), provided that x is not free in φ.



      Now, I understand how to derive these equivalences syntactically. However, I can't seem to grasp how the first two can be semantically equivalent.

      For example, how can two sentences such as "If all x are wet, then it's raining" and "There exists an x such that if x is wet, then it's raining" can be equivalent?

      Moreover, provided that x is not free in ψ, isn't (∀x)φ(x) → ψ equivalent to (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ)? Which would result in the absurd equivalence: (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ) ⇔ (∃x)(φ(x) → ψ).



      I think that my difficulty here arises from a misunderstanding of the significance of the parentheses in the aforementioned equivalences. Please provide examples in your answer if you can.










      share|improve this question









      New contributor




      Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
      Check out our Code of Conduct.











      I know that the rules for removing quantifiers from the antecedent of a conditional are as follows:
      (∀x)φ(x) → ψ ⇔ (∃x)(φ(x) → ψ) and (∃x)φ(x) → ψ ⇔ (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ), provided that x is not free in ψ.
      I also know that the rules for removing quantifiers from the consequent are as follows:
      φ → (∀x)ψ(x) ⇔ (∀x)(φ → ψ(x)) and φ → (∃x)ψ(x) ⇔ (∃x)(φ → ψ(x)), provided that x is not free in φ.



      Now, I understand how to derive these equivalences syntactically. However, I can't seem to grasp how the first two can be semantically equivalent.

      For example, how can two sentences such as "If all x are wet, then it's raining" and "There exists an x such that if x is wet, then it's raining" can be equivalent?

      Moreover, provided that x is not free in ψ, isn't (∀x)φ(x) → ψ equivalent to (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ)? Which would result in the absurd equivalence: (∀x)(φ(x) → ψ) ⇔ (∃x)(φ(x) → ψ).



      I think that my difficulty here arises from a misunderstanding of the significance of the parentheses in the aforementioned equivalences. Please provide examples in your answer if you can.







      logic






      share|improve this question









      New contributor




      Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
      Check out our Code of Conduct.











      share|improve this question









      New contributor




      Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
      Check out our Code of Conduct.









      share|improve this question




      share|improve this question








      edited 2 days ago





















      New contributor




      Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
      Check out our Code of Conduct.









      asked 2 days ago









      Ofek Aman

      334




      334




      New contributor




      Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
      Check out our Code of Conduct.





      New contributor





      Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
      Check out our Code of Conduct.






      Ofek Aman is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
      Check out our Code of Conduct.






















          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes

















          up vote
          6
          down vote



          accepted











          how can two sentences such as "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" and "There exists an x such that (if x is wet, then it's raining)" can be equivalent?




          A simple approach to this equivalence, that holds only in classical logic, is to exploit the so-called Material implication rule :




          (P → Q) ≡ (¬ P ∨ Q).




          Thus, we have that : "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" is equivalent to : "Either (not all x are wet) or it's raining", i.e "Either (there exists an x which is not wet) or it's raining".



          Now we have to use the fact that the existential quantifier "distribute" over or and the fact that "it's is raining" is equivalent to "there is an x such that it's raining", due to the key-fact that x is not free in "it's raining".



          Thus, the last step is to move the existential quantifier in front of the formula to get :




          "There exists an x such that (either x is not wet or it's raining)."






          We can show the semantical equivalence of :




          (∀x βx → α) ↔ ∃x(βx → α)




          this way.



          Let M a structure whatever, with domain D.



          Two cases :



          (i) ∀x βx is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          This means that there is an a in D such that βa is False.



          Thus, (βa → α) is True, which means that (βx → α) is True for some x.



          And thus, also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (ii) ∀x βx is True.



          Two subcases :



          (iia) α is True. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          But if α is True, also (βx → α), irrespective of the value of x, and thus also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (iib) α is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is False.



          The fact that ∀x βx is True imples that βa is True, for every a in D.



          Thus (βa → α) is False, for every a in D, which means that ∃x(βx → α) is False.






          share|improve this answer



















          • 1




            Thank you for clarifying the problem. I understand how the universal conditional implies the existential so no problem here. However, I still don't get how the existential conditional also implies the universal.
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago










          • @OfekAman - not clear... the two are equivalent : when (∀x βx → α) is True, also ∃x(βx → α) is True. When (∀x βx → α) is False, also ∃x(βx → α) is False.
            – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
            2 days ago












          • Oh, I see it now. The two expressions always get yhe same truth value and therefore are equivalent. Thank you!
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago











          Your Answer








          StackExchange.ready(function() {
          var channelOptions = {
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "265"
          };
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
          createEditor();
          });
          }
          else {
          createEditor();
          }
          });

          function createEditor() {
          StackExchange.prepareEditor({
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          convertImagesToLinks: false,
          noModals: true,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: null,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          imageUploader: {
          brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
          contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
          allowUrls: true
          },
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          });


          }
          });






          Ofek Aman is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f57423%2fdifficulty-with-understanding-the-semantics-of-the-following-equivalences%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown

























          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes








          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes








          up vote
          6
          down vote



          accepted











          how can two sentences such as "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" and "There exists an x such that (if x is wet, then it's raining)" can be equivalent?




          A simple approach to this equivalence, that holds only in classical logic, is to exploit the so-called Material implication rule :




          (P → Q) ≡ (¬ P ∨ Q).




          Thus, we have that : "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" is equivalent to : "Either (not all x are wet) or it's raining", i.e "Either (there exists an x which is not wet) or it's raining".



          Now we have to use the fact that the existential quantifier "distribute" over or and the fact that "it's is raining" is equivalent to "there is an x such that it's raining", due to the key-fact that x is not free in "it's raining".



          Thus, the last step is to move the existential quantifier in front of the formula to get :




          "There exists an x such that (either x is not wet or it's raining)."






          We can show the semantical equivalence of :




          (∀x βx → α) ↔ ∃x(βx → α)




          this way.



          Let M a structure whatever, with domain D.



          Two cases :



          (i) ∀x βx is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          This means that there is an a in D such that βa is False.



          Thus, (βa → α) is True, which means that (βx → α) is True for some x.



          And thus, also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (ii) ∀x βx is True.



          Two subcases :



          (iia) α is True. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          But if α is True, also (βx → α), irrespective of the value of x, and thus also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (iib) α is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is False.



          The fact that ∀x βx is True imples that βa is True, for every a in D.



          Thus (βa → α) is False, for every a in D, which means that ∃x(βx → α) is False.






          share|improve this answer



















          • 1




            Thank you for clarifying the problem. I understand how the universal conditional implies the existential so no problem here. However, I still don't get how the existential conditional also implies the universal.
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago










          • @OfekAman - not clear... the two are equivalent : when (∀x βx → α) is True, also ∃x(βx → α) is True. When (∀x βx → α) is False, also ∃x(βx → α) is False.
            – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
            2 days ago












          • Oh, I see it now. The two expressions always get yhe same truth value and therefore are equivalent. Thank you!
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago















          up vote
          6
          down vote



          accepted











          how can two sentences such as "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" and "There exists an x such that (if x is wet, then it's raining)" can be equivalent?




          A simple approach to this equivalence, that holds only in classical logic, is to exploit the so-called Material implication rule :




          (P → Q) ≡ (¬ P ∨ Q).




          Thus, we have that : "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" is equivalent to : "Either (not all x are wet) or it's raining", i.e "Either (there exists an x which is not wet) or it's raining".



          Now we have to use the fact that the existential quantifier "distribute" over or and the fact that "it's is raining" is equivalent to "there is an x such that it's raining", due to the key-fact that x is not free in "it's raining".



          Thus, the last step is to move the existential quantifier in front of the formula to get :




          "There exists an x such that (either x is not wet or it's raining)."






          We can show the semantical equivalence of :




          (∀x βx → α) ↔ ∃x(βx → α)




          this way.



          Let M a structure whatever, with domain D.



          Two cases :



          (i) ∀x βx is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          This means that there is an a in D such that βa is False.



          Thus, (βa → α) is True, which means that (βx → α) is True for some x.



          And thus, also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (ii) ∀x βx is True.



          Two subcases :



          (iia) α is True. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          But if α is True, also (βx → α), irrespective of the value of x, and thus also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (iib) α is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is False.



          The fact that ∀x βx is True imples that βa is True, for every a in D.



          Thus (βa → α) is False, for every a in D, which means that ∃x(βx → α) is False.






          share|improve this answer



















          • 1




            Thank you for clarifying the problem. I understand how the universal conditional implies the existential so no problem here. However, I still don't get how the existential conditional also implies the universal.
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago










          • @OfekAman - not clear... the two are equivalent : when (∀x βx → α) is True, also ∃x(βx → α) is True. When (∀x βx → α) is False, also ∃x(βx → α) is False.
            – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
            2 days ago












          • Oh, I see it now. The two expressions always get yhe same truth value and therefore are equivalent. Thank you!
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago













          up vote
          6
          down vote



          accepted







          up vote
          6
          down vote



          accepted







          how can two sentences such as "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" and "There exists an x such that (if x is wet, then it's raining)" can be equivalent?




          A simple approach to this equivalence, that holds only in classical logic, is to exploit the so-called Material implication rule :




          (P → Q) ≡ (¬ P ∨ Q).




          Thus, we have that : "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" is equivalent to : "Either (not all x are wet) or it's raining", i.e "Either (there exists an x which is not wet) or it's raining".



          Now we have to use the fact that the existential quantifier "distribute" over or and the fact that "it's is raining" is equivalent to "there is an x such that it's raining", due to the key-fact that x is not free in "it's raining".



          Thus, the last step is to move the existential quantifier in front of the formula to get :




          "There exists an x such that (either x is not wet or it's raining)."






          We can show the semantical equivalence of :




          (∀x βx → α) ↔ ∃x(βx → α)




          this way.



          Let M a structure whatever, with domain D.



          Two cases :



          (i) ∀x βx is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          This means that there is an a in D such that βa is False.



          Thus, (βa → α) is True, which means that (βx → α) is True for some x.



          And thus, also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (ii) ∀x βx is True.



          Two subcases :



          (iia) α is True. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          But if α is True, also (βx → α), irrespective of the value of x, and thus also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (iib) α is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is False.



          The fact that ∀x βx is True imples that βa is True, for every a in D.



          Thus (βa → α) is False, for every a in D, which means that ∃x(βx → α) is False.






          share|improve this answer















          how can two sentences such as "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" and "There exists an x such that (if x is wet, then it's raining)" can be equivalent?




          A simple approach to this equivalence, that holds only in classical logic, is to exploit the so-called Material implication rule :




          (P → Q) ≡ (¬ P ∨ Q).




          Thus, we have that : "(If all x are wet, then it's raining)" is equivalent to : "Either (not all x are wet) or it's raining", i.e "Either (there exists an x which is not wet) or it's raining".



          Now we have to use the fact that the existential quantifier "distribute" over or and the fact that "it's is raining" is equivalent to "there is an x such that it's raining", due to the key-fact that x is not free in "it's raining".



          Thus, the last step is to move the existential quantifier in front of the formula to get :




          "There exists an x such that (either x is not wet or it's raining)."






          We can show the semantical equivalence of :




          (∀x βx → α) ↔ ∃x(βx → α)




          this way.



          Let M a structure whatever, with domain D.



          Two cases :



          (i) ∀x βx is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          This means that there is an a in D such that βa is False.



          Thus, (βa → α) is True, which means that (βx → α) is True for some x.



          And thus, also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (ii) ∀x βx is True.



          Two subcases :



          (iia) α is True. In this case (∀x βx → α) is True.



          But if α is True, also (βx → α), irrespective of the value of x, and thus also ∃x(βx → α) is True.



          (iib) α is False. In this case (∀x βx → α) is False.



          The fact that ∀x βx is True imples that βa is True, for every a in D.



          Thus (βa → α) is False, for every a in D, which means that ∃x(βx → α) is False.







          share|improve this answer














          share|improve this answer



          share|improve this answer








          edited 2 days ago

























          answered 2 days ago









          Mauro ALLEGRANZA

          26.9k21860




          26.9k21860








          • 1




            Thank you for clarifying the problem. I understand how the universal conditional implies the existential so no problem here. However, I still don't get how the existential conditional also implies the universal.
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago










          • @OfekAman - not clear... the two are equivalent : when (∀x βx → α) is True, also ∃x(βx → α) is True. When (∀x βx → α) is False, also ∃x(βx → α) is False.
            – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
            2 days ago












          • Oh, I see it now. The two expressions always get yhe same truth value and therefore are equivalent. Thank you!
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago














          • 1




            Thank you for clarifying the problem. I understand how the universal conditional implies the existential so no problem here. However, I still don't get how the existential conditional also implies the universal.
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago










          • @OfekAman - not clear... the two are equivalent : when (∀x βx → α) is True, also ∃x(βx → α) is True. When (∀x βx → α) is False, also ∃x(βx → α) is False.
            – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
            2 days ago












          • Oh, I see it now. The two expressions always get yhe same truth value and therefore are equivalent. Thank you!
            – Ofek Aman
            2 days ago








          1




          1




          Thank you for clarifying the problem. I understand how the universal conditional implies the existential so no problem here. However, I still don't get how the existential conditional also implies the universal.
          – Ofek Aman
          2 days ago




          Thank you for clarifying the problem. I understand how the universal conditional implies the existential so no problem here. However, I still don't get how the existential conditional also implies the universal.
          – Ofek Aman
          2 days ago












          @OfekAman - not clear... the two are equivalent : when (∀x βx → α) is True, also ∃x(βx → α) is True. When (∀x βx → α) is False, also ∃x(βx → α) is False.
          – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
          2 days ago






          @OfekAman - not clear... the two are equivalent : when (∀x βx → α) is True, also ∃x(βx → α) is True. When (∀x βx → α) is False, also ∃x(βx → α) is False.
          – Mauro ALLEGRANZA
          2 days ago














          Oh, I see it now. The two expressions always get yhe same truth value and therefore are equivalent. Thank you!
          – Ofek Aman
          2 days ago




          Oh, I see it now. The two expressions always get yhe same truth value and therefore are equivalent. Thank you!
          – Ofek Aman
          2 days ago










          Ofek Aman is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


















          Ofek Aman is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.













          Ofek Aman is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.












          Ofek Aman is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.















           


          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f57423%2fdifficulty-with-understanding-the-semantics-of-the-following-equivalences%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest















          Required, but never shown





















































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown

































          Required, but never shown














          Required, but never shown












          Required, but never shown







          Required, but never shown







          Popular posts from this blog

          "Incorrect syntax near the keyword 'ON'. (on update cascade, on delete cascade,)

          Alcedinidae

          RAC Tourist Trophy