How come particles are not constantly “measured” by the whole universe?












12












$begingroup$


Let's say we are doing the double slit experiment with electrons. We get an interference pattern, and if we put detectors at slits, then we get two piles pattern because we measure electrons' positions when going through slits. But an electron interacts with other particles in a lot of different ways, e.g. electric field, gravity. Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position. Why is it not the case and the electron goes through slits "unmeasured"?



Bonus question: in real experiments do we face the problem of not "shielding" particles from "measurement" good enough and thus getting a mix of both patterns on the screen?










share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Very closely related question here. It's basically the same idea, but specialized to a particular apparatus.
    $endgroup$
    – knzhou
    10 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    Measurement doesn't do anything. See related questions physics.stackexchange.com/questions/453410/… and physics.stackexchange.com/questions/459754/…
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    6 hours ago
















12












$begingroup$


Let's say we are doing the double slit experiment with electrons. We get an interference pattern, and if we put detectors at slits, then we get two piles pattern because we measure electrons' positions when going through slits. But an electron interacts with other particles in a lot of different ways, e.g. electric field, gravity. Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position. Why is it not the case and the electron goes through slits "unmeasured"?



Bonus question: in real experiments do we face the problem of not "shielding" particles from "measurement" good enough and thus getting a mix of both patterns on the screen?










share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Very closely related question here. It's basically the same idea, but specialized to a particular apparatus.
    $endgroup$
    – knzhou
    10 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    Measurement doesn't do anything. See related questions physics.stackexchange.com/questions/453410/… and physics.stackexchange.com/questions/459754/…
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    6 hours ago














12












12








12


4



$begingroup$


Let's say we are doing the double slit experiment with electrons. We get an interference pattern, and if we put detectors at slits, then we get two piles pattern because we measure electrons' positions when going through slits. But an electron interacts with other particles in a lot of different ways, e.g. electric field, gravity. Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position. Why is it not the case and the electron goes through slits "unmeasured"?



Bonus question: in real experiments do we face the problem of not "shielding" particles from "measurement" good enough and thus getting a mix of both patterns on the screen?










share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.







$endgroup$




Let's say we are doing the double slit experiment with electrons. We get an interference pattern, and if we put detectors at slits, then we get two piles pattern because we measure electrons' positions when going through slits. But an electron interacts with other particles in a lot of different ways, e.g. electric field, gravity. Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position. Why is it not the case and the electron goes through slits "unmeasured"?



Bonus question: in real experiments do we face the problem of not "shielding" particles from "measurement" good enough and thus getting a mix of both patterns on the screen?







quantum-mechanics double-slit-experiment measurement-problem






share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.











share|cite|improve this question







New contributor




FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question






New contributor




FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









asked 10 hours ago









FunkyLoisoFunkyLoiso

612




612




New contributor




FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





New contributor





FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






FunkyLoiso is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Very closely related question here. It's basically the same idea, but specialized to a particular apparatus.
    $endgroup$
    – knzhou
    10 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    Measurement doesn't do anything. See related questions physics.stackexchange.com/questions/453410/… and physics.stackexchange.com/questions/459754/…
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    6 hours ago














  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Very closely related question here. It's basically the same idea, but specialized to a particular apparatus.
    $endgroup$
    – knzhou
    10 hours ago










  • $begingroup$
    Measurement doesn't do anything. See related questions physics.stackexchange.com/questions/453410/… and physics.stackexchange.com/questions/459754/…
    $endgroup$
    – R..
    6 hours ago








1




1




$begingroup$
Very closely related question here. It's basically the same idea, but specialized to a particular apparatus.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
10 hours ago




$begingroup$
Very closely related question here. It's basically the same idea, but specialized to a particular apparatus.
$endgroup$
– knzhou
10 hours ago












$begingroup$
Measurement doesn't do anything. See related questions physics.stackexchange.com/questions/453410/… and physics.stackexchange.com/questions/459754/…
$endgroup$
– R..
6 hours ago




$begingroup$
Measurement doesn't do anything. See related questions physics.stackexchange.com/questions/453410/… and physics.stackexchange.com/questions/459754/…
$endgroup$
– R..
6 hours ago










4 Answers
4






active

oldest

votes


















7












$begingroup$

There are time-scales related to interactions, or, equivalently, interaction rates. An experiment that measures electron interference needs to make sure that the time-of-flight of the electrons from the electron source to the observation screen is much shorter than any of the time-scales of possible interactions.



In interference experiments, we therefore define a coherence time for the interfering particles.



In real experiments, we do indeed face the problem of shielding particles from being measured by the environment, before they interfere. For example, in electron interferometers realized in solid-state devices, we have to go to very low temperatures, where the interactions between electrons and phonons become very 'slow' (their rate becomes very small). We also have to make sure that the devices are small enough that the Coulomb-interaction between electrons, which persists even at the lowest temperatures, does not spoil the interference (the decoherence rate due to electron-electron interaction does also depend on temperature: the rate becomes smaller with decreasing temperature).






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$









  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Could you please explain the interaction rates? Let's think about gravitational interaction between the electron and the slits themselves. Naive thinking tells me that the electron exerts gravitational pull on the slits. The slit the electron went through experiences more pull and gets more deformation, which can potentially be measured had we good enough tools. This looks to me like an infinite interaction rate, the pull is smoothly increasing over time. Is the pull actually quantified and is there a probability of 0 quanta exchanged? Or maybe the pull is in superposition itself?
    $endgroup$
    – FunkyLoiso
    9 hours ago






  • 5




    $begingroup$
    Nice, +1. And to address the OP's question about whether this means that particles are "measured" -- the notion of measurement and wavefunction collapse in the Copenhagen interpretation never made much sense, because there was no way to say what was a "measurement." This has been clarified by understanding of decoherence, which is basically what flaudemus is describing.
    $endgroup$
    – Ben Crowell
    8 hours ago



















2












$begingroup$

Distinguishing which slit is which is the factor that causes the wavelike interference pattern to disappear. Experiments show that the more the path can be determined the more they look like single photons.



Here's some notes on a course where this is worked out explicitly for a Mach-Zender quantum interference experiment, where this continuum between "classical" and "quantum" is made mathematically explicit.



So yes, the more the experiment's electrons interacts with the "universe" in a way that the "universe" can gain information about which slit it went through, the more the "quantum interference pattern" disappears. This is a good intuition for why things at a macroscopic level behave classically: because the individual quantum pieces are interacting with the environment so much that all of this "quantum perserving" information leaks out.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$





















    1












    $begingroup$


    Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position.




    Yes, the influence that an electron exerts on the rest of the universe does depend on the location of the electron, but that's not enough to constitute a measurement of the electron's location. We need to consider the degree to which the electron's influence on the rest of the universe depends on its location.



    Consider something analogous to but simpler than a double slit experiment: consider an electron in deep space, in a superposition of two different locations $A$ and $B$. Even in deep space, the electron is not alone, because space is filled with cosmic microwave background (CMB) radiation. CMB radiation has a typical wavelength of about $1$ millimeter. When CMB radiation is scattered by an electron, the resulting state of the radiation depends on the electron's location, but the key question is how much it depends on the electron's location. If the locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $gg 1$ millimeter, then the CMB radiation will measure the electron's location very effectively, because an electron in location $A$ will have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. But if locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $ll 1$ millimeter, then an electron in location $A$ will not have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. Sure, the electron has a significant effect on the CMB radiation regardless of its location, but that key is whether the effect differs significantly when the location is $A$ versus $B$. The CMB radiation measures the electron's location, but it does so with limited resolution. Widely-spaced locations will be measured very effectively, but closely-separated locations will not.



    For this to really make sense, words are not enough. We need to consider the math. So here's a version that includes a smidgen of math.



    Let $|arangle$ denote the state of the universe (including the electron) that would result if the electron's location were $A$, and let $|brangle$ denote the state of the universe that would result if the electron's location were $B$. If the electron started in some superposition of locations $A$ and $B$, then the resulting state of the universe will be something like $|arangle+|brangle$. Whether or not the electon's location is effectively measured, these two terms will be essentially orthogonal to each other, $langle a|brangleapprox 0$, simply because they differ significantly in the location of the electron itself. So the fact that the final state is $|arangle+|brangle$ with $langle a|brangleapprox 0$ doesn't tell us anything about whether or not the electron's location was actually measured. For that, we need a principle like this:




    • The electron's location has been effectively measured if and only if the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are such that $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$ for all feasibly-measurable future observables $hat O$. (Quantifying "$approx 0$" requires some care, but I won't go into those details here.)


    For an operator $hat O$ to be "feasibly measurable", it must be sufficiently simple, which loosely means that it does not require determining too many details over too large a region of space. This is a fuzzy definition, of course, as is the definition of measurement itself, but this fuzziness doesn't cause any problems in practice. (The fact that it doesn't cause any problems in practice is frustrating, because this makes the measurement process itself very difficult to study experimentally!)



    In the example described above, the suggested condition is satisfied if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $gg 1$ millimeter, because after enough CMB radiation has been scattered by the electron, the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ differ significantly from each other everywhere, and no operator $hat O$ that is simple enough to represent a feasibly-measurable observable can possibly un-do the orthogonality of the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$. Loosely speaking, the state $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ aren't just orthogonal; they're prolifically orthogonal, in a way that can't be un-done by any simple operator. In contrast, if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $ll 1$ millimeter, then we can choose an operator $hat O$ that acts just on the electron (and is therefore relatively simple) to obtain $hat O|arangleapprox |brangle$, thus violating the condition $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$. So in this case, the electron's location has not been effectively measured at all. The states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are orthogonal simply because they differ in the location of the electron itself, but they are not prolifically orthogonal because the effect on the rest of the universe doesn't depend significantly on whether the electron's location was $A$ versus $B$.



    What I'm doing here is describing "decoherence" in a different way than it is usually described. The way I'm describing it here doesn't rely on any factorization of the Hilbert space into the "system of interest" and "everything else." The way I'm describing it here (after quantifying some of my loose statements more carefully) can be applied more generally. It doesn't solve the infamous measurement problem (which has to do with the impossibility of deriving Born's rule within quantum theory), but it does allow us to determine how effectively a given observable has been measured.



    Some quantitative calculations — including quantitative results for the specific example I used here — are described in Tegmark's paper "Apparent wave function collapse caused by scattering" (https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9310032), which is briefly reviewed in https://physics.stackexchange.com/a/442464. Those calculations use the more traditional description of decoherence, but the results are equally applicable to the way I described things here.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$





















      0












      $begingroup$

      As long as these interactions are weak and do not distinguish between the two slits, they can be disregarded.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$













        Your Answer





        StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
        return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
        StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
        StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
        });
        });
        }, "mathjax-editing");

        StackExchange.ready(function() {
        var channelOptions = {
        tags: "".split(" "),
        id: "151"
        };
        initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

        StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
        // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
        if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
        StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
        createEditor();
        });
        }
        else {
        createEditor();
        }
        });

        function createEditor() {
        StackExchange.prepareEditor({
        heartbeatType: 'answer',
        autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
        convertImagesToLinks: false,
        noModals: true,
        showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
        reputationToPostImages: null,
        bindNavPrevention: true,
        postfix: "",
        imageUploader: {
        brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
        contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
        allowUrls: true
        },
        noCode: true, onDemand: true,
        discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
        ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
        });


        }
        });






        FunkyLoiso is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










        draft saved

        draft discarded


















        StackExchange.ready(
        function () {
        StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphysics.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f460855%2fhow-come-particles-are-not-constantly-measured-by-the-whole-universe%23new-answer', 'question_page');
        }
        );

        Post as a guest















        Required, but never shown

























        4 Answers
        4






        active

        oldest

        votes








        4 Answers
        4






        active

        oldest

        votes









        active

        oldest

        votes






        active

        oldest

        votes









        7












        $begingroup$

        There are time-scales related to interactions, or, equivalently, interaction rates. An experiment that measures electron interference needs to make sure that the time-of-flight of the electrons from the electron source to the observation screen is much shorter than any of the time-scales of possible interactions.



        In interference experiments, we therefore define a coherence time for the interfering particles.



        In real experiments, we do indeed face the problem of shielding particles from being measured by the environment, before they interfere. For example, in electron interferometers realized in solid-state devices, we have to go to very low temperatures, where the interactions between electrons and phonons become very 'slow' (their rate becomes very small). We also have to make sure that the devices are small enough that the Coulomb-interaction between electrons, which persists even at the lowest temperatures, does not spoil the interference (the decoherence rate due to electron-electron interaction does also depend on temperature: the rate becomes smaller with decreasing temperature).






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$









        • 1




          $begingroup$
          Could you please explain the interaction rates? Let's think about gravitational interaction between the electron and the slits themselves. Naive thinking tells me that the electron exerts gravitational pull on the slits. The slit the electron went through experiences more pull and gets more deformation, which can potentially be measured had we good enough tools. This looks to me like an infinite interaction rate, the pull is smoothly increasing over time. Is the pull actually quantified and is there a probability of 0 quanta exchanged? Or maybe the pull is in superposition itself?
          $endgroup$
          – FunkyLoiso
          9 hours ago






        • 5




          $begingroup$
          Nice, +1. And to address the OP's question about whether this means that particles are "measured" -- the notion of measurement and wavefunction collapse in the Copenhagen interpretation never made much sense, because there was no way to say what was a "measurement." This has been clarified by understanding of decoherence, which is basically what flaudemus is describing.
          $endgroup$
          – Ben Crowell
          8 hours ago
















        7












        $begingroup$

        There are time-scales related to interactions, or, equivalently, interaction rates. An experiment that measures electron interference needs to make sure that the time-of-flight of the electrons from the electron source to the observation screen is much shorter than any of the time-scales of possible interactions.



        In interference experiments, we therefore define a coherence time for the interfering particles.



        In real experiments, we do indeed face the problem of shielding particles from being measured by the environment, before they interfere. For example, in electron interferometers realized in solid-state devices, we have to go to very low temperatures, where the interactions between electrons and phonons become very 'slow' (their rate becomes very small). We also have to make sure that the devices are small enough that the Coulomb-interaction between electrons, which persists even at the lowest temperatures, does not spoil the interference (the decoherence rate due to electron-electron interaction does also depend on temperature: the rate becomes smaller with decreasing temperature).






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$









        • 1




          $begingroup$
          Could you please explain the interaction rates? Let's think about gravitational interaction between the electron and the slits themselves. Naive thinking tells me that the electron exerts gravitational pull on the slits. The slit the electron went through experiences more pull and gets more deformation, which can potentially be measured had we good enough tools. This looks to me like an infinite interaction rate, the pull is smoothly increasing over time. Is the pull actually quantified and is there a probability of 0 quanta exchanged? Or maybe the pull is in superposition itself?
          $endgroup$
          – FunkyLoiso
          9 hours ago






        • 5




          $begingroup$
          Nice, +1. And to address the OP's question about whether this means that particles are "measured" -- the notion of measurement and wavefunction collapse in the Copenhagen interpretation never made much sense, because there was no way to say what was a "measurement." This has been clarified by understanding of decoherence, which is basically what flaudemus is describing.
          $endgroup$
          – Ben Crowell
          8 hours ago














        7












        7








        7





        $begingroup$

        There are time-scales related to interactions, or, equivalently, interaction rates. An experiment that measures electron interference needs to make sure that the time-of-flight of the electrons from the electron source to the observation screen is much shorter than any of the time-scales of possible interactions.



        In interference experiments, we therefore define a coherence time for the interfering particles.



        In real experiments, we do indeed face the problem of shielding particles from being measured by the environment, before they interfere. For example, in electron interferometers realized in solid-state devices, we have to go to very low temperatures, where the interactions between electrons and phonons become very 'slow' (their rate becomes very small). We also have to make sure that the devices are small enough that the Coulomb-interaction between electrons, which persists even at the lowest temperatures, does not spoil the interference (the decoherence rate due to electron-electron interaction does also depend on temperature: the rate becomes smaller with decreasing temperature).






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        There are time-scales related to interactions, or, equivalently, interaction rates. An experiment that measures electron interference needs to make sure that the time-of-flight of the electrons from the electron source to the observation screen is much shorter than any of the time-scales of possible interactions.



        In interference experiments, we therefore define a coherence time for the interfering particles.



        In real experiments, we do indeed face the problem of shielding particles from being measured by the environment, before they interfere. For example, in electron interferometers realized in solid-state devices, we have to go to very low temperatures, where the interactions between electrons and phonons become very 'slow' (their rate becomes very small). We also have to make sure that the devices are small enough that the Coulomb-interaction between electrons, which persists even at the lowest temperatures, does not spoil the interference (the decoherence rate due to electron-electron interaction does also depend on temperature: the rate becomes smaller with decreasing temperature).







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered 9 hours ago









        flaudemusflaudemus

        2925




        2925








        • 1




          $begingroup$
          Could you please explain the interaction rates? Let's think about gravitational interaction between the electron and the slits themselves. Naive thinking tells me that the electron exerts gravitational pull on the slits. The slit the electron went through experiences more pull and gets more deformation, which can potentially be measured had we good enough tools. This looks to me like an infinite interaction rate, the pull is smoothly increasing over time. Is the pull actually quantified and is there a probability of 0 quanta exchanged? Or maybe the pull is in superposition itself?
          $endgroup$
          – FunkyLoiso
          9 hours ago






        • 5




          $begingroup$
          Nice, +1. And to address the OP's question about whether this means that particles are "measured" -- the notion of measurement and wavefunction collapse in the Copenhagen interpretation never made much sense, because there was no way to say what was a "measurement." This has been clarified by understanding of decoherence, which is basically what flaudemus is describing.
          $endgroup$
          – Ben Crowell
          8 hours ago














        • 1




          $begingroup$
          Could you please explain the interaction rates? Let's think about gravitational interaction between the electron and the slits themselves. Naive thinking tells me that the electron exerts gravitational pull on the slits. The slit the electron went through experiences more pull and gets more deformation, which can potentially be measured had we good enough tools. This looks to me like an infinite interaction rate, the pull is smoothly increasing over time. Is the pull actually quantified and is there a probability of 0 quanta exchanged? Or maybe the pull is in superposition itself?
          $endgroup$
          – FunkyLoiso
          9 hours ago






        • 5




          $begingroup$
          Nice, +1. And to address the OP's question about whether this means that particles are "measured" -- the notion of measurement and wavefunction collapse in the Copenhagen interpretation never made much sense, because there was no way to say what was a "measurement." This has been clarified by understanding of decoherence, which is basically what flaudemus is describing.
          $endgroup$
          – Ben Crowell
          8 hours ago








        1




        1




        $begingroup$
        Could you please explain the interaction rates? Let's think about gravitational interaction between the electron and the slits themselves. Naive thinking tells me that the electron exerts gravitational pull on the slits. The slit the electron went through experiences more pull and gets more deformation, which can potentially be measured had we good enough tools. This looks to me like an infinite interaction rate, the pull is smoothly increasing over time. Is the pull actually quantified and is there a probability of 0 quanta exchanged? Or maybe the pull is in superposition itself?
        $endgroup$
        – FunkyLoiso
        9 hours ago




        $begingroup$
        Could you please explain the interaction rates? Let's think about gravitational interaction between the electron and the slits themselves. Naive thinking tells me that the electron exerts gravitational pull on the slits. The slit the electron went through experiences more pull and gets more deformation, which can potentially be measured had we good enough tools. This looks to me like an infinite interaction rate, the pull is smoothly increasing over time. Is the pull actually quantified and is there a probability of 0 quanta exchanged? Or maybe the pull is in superposition itself?
        $endgroup$
        – FunkyLoiso
        9 hours ago




        5




        5




        $begingroup$
        Nice, +1. And to address the OP's question about whether this means that particles are "measured" -- the notion of measurement and wavefunction collapse in the Copenhagen interpretation never made much sense, because there was no way to say what was a "measurement." This has been clarified by understanding of decoherence, which is basically what flaudemus is describing.
        $endgroup$
        – Ben Crowell
        8 hours ago




        $begingroup$
        Nice, +1. And to address the OP's question about whether this means that particles are "measured" -- the notion of measurement and wavefunction collapse in the Copenhagen interpretation never made much sense, because there was no way to say what was a "measurement." This has been clarified by understanding of decoherence, which is basically what flaudemus is describing.
        $endgroup$
        – Ben Crowell
        8 hours ago











        2












        $begingroup$

        Distinguishing which slit is which is the factor that causes the wavelike interference pattern to disappear. Experiments show that the more the path can be determined the more they look like single photons.



        Here's some notes on a course where this is worked out explicitly for a Mach-Zender quantum interference experiment, where this continuum between "classical" and "quantum" is made mathematically explicit.



        So yes, the more the experiment's electrons interacts with the "universe" in a way that the "universe" can gain information about which slit it went through, the more the "quantum interference pattern" disappears. This is a good intuition for why things at a macroscopic level behave classically: because the individual quantum pieces are interacting with the environment so much that all of this "quantum perserving" information leaks out.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$


















          2












          $begingroup$

          Distinguishing which slit is which is the factor that causes the wavelike interference pattern to disappear. Experiments show that the more the path can be determined the more they look like single photons.



          Here's some notes on a course where this is worked out explicitly for a Mach-Zender quantum interference experiment, where this continuum between "classical" and "quantum" is made mathematically explicit.



          So yes, the more the experiment's electrons interacts with the "universe" in a way that the "universe" can gain information about which slit it went through, the more the "quantum interference pattern" disappears. This is a good intuition for why things at a macroscopic level behave classically: because the individual quantum pieces are interacting with the environment so much that all of this "quantum perserving" information leaks out.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$
















            2












            2








            2





            $begingroup$

            Distinguishing which slit is which is the factor that causes the wavelike interference pattern to disappear. Experiments show that the more the path can be determined the more they look like single photons.



            Here's some notes on a course where this is worked out explicitly for a Mach-Zender quantum interference experiment, where this continuum between "classical" and "quantum" is made mathematically explicit.



            So yes, the more the experiment's electrons interacts with the "universe" in a way that the "universe" can gain information about which slit it went through, the more the "quantum interference pattern" disappears. This is a good intuition for why things at a macroscopic level behave classically: because the individual quantum pieces are interacting with the environment so much that all of this "quantum perserving" information leaks out.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$



            Distinguishing which slit is which is the factor that causes the wavelike interference pattern to disappear. Experiments show that the more the path can be determined the more they look like single photons.



            Here's some notes on a course where this is worked out explicitly for a Mach-Zender quantum interference experiment, where this continuum between "classical" and "quantum" is made mathematically explicit.



            So yes, the more the experiment's electrons interacts with the "universe" in a way that the "universe" can gain information about which slit it went through, the more the "quantum interference pattern" disappears. This is a good intuition for why things at a macroscopic level behave classically: because the individual quantum pieces are interacting with the environment so much that all of this "quantum perserving" information leaks out.







            share|cite|improve this answer












            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer










            answered 10 hours ago









            Steven SagonaSteven Sagona

            220217




            220217























                1












                $begingroup$


                Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position.




                Yes, the influence that an electron exerts on the rest of the universe does depend on the location of the electron, but that's not enough to constitute a measurement of the electron's location. We need to consider the degree to which the electron's influence on the rest of the universe depends on its location.



                Consider something analogous to but simpler than a double slit experiment: consider an electron in deep space, in a superposition of two different locations $A$ and $B$. Even in deep space, the electron is not alone, because space is filled with cosmic microwave background (CMB) radiation. CMB radiation has a typical wavelength of about $1$ millimeter. When CMB radiation is scattered by an electron, the resulting state of the radiation depends on the electron's location, but the key question is how much it depends on the electron's location. If the locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $gg 1$ millimeter, then the CMB radiation will measure the electron's location very effectively, because an electron in location $A$ will have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. But if locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $ll 1$ millimeter, then an electron in location $A$ will not have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. Sure, the electron has a significant effect on the CMB radiation regardless of its location, but that key is whether the effect differs significantly when the location is $A$ versus $B$. The CMB radiation measures the electron's location, but it does so with limited resolution. Widely-spaced locations will be measured very effectively, but closely-separated locations will not.



                For this to really make sense, words are not enough. We need to consider the math. So here's a version that includes a smidgen of math.



                Let $|arangle$ denote the state of the universe (including the electron) that would result if the electron's location were $A$, and let $|brangle$ denote the state of the universe that would result if the electron's location were $B$. If the electron started in some superposition of locations $A$ and $B$, then the resulting state of the universe will be something like $|arangle+|brangle$. Whether or not the electon's location is effectively measured, these two terms will be essentially orthogonal to each other, $langle a|brangleapprox 0$, simply because they differ significantly in the location of the electron itself. So the fact that the final state is $|arangle+|brangle$ with $langle a|brangleapprox 0$ doesn't tell us anything about whether or not the electron's location was actually measured. For that, we need a principle like this:




                • The electron's location has been effectively measured if and only if the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are such that $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$ for all feasibly-measurable future observables $hat O$. (Quantifying "$approx 0$" requires some care, but I won't go into those details here.)


                For an operator $hat O$ to be "feasibly measurable", it must be sufficiently simple, which loosely means that it does not require determining too many details over too large a region of space. This is a fuzzy definition, of course, as is the definition of measurement itself, but this fuzziness doesn't cause any problems in practice. (The fact that it doesn't cause any problems in practice is frustrating, because this makes the measurement process itself very difficult to study experimentally!)



                In the example described above, the suggested condition is satisfied if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $gg 1$ millimeter, because after enough CMB radiation has been scattered by the electron, the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ differ significantly from each other everywhere, and no operator $hat O$ that is simple enough to represent a feasibly-measurable observable can possibly un-do the orthogonality of the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$. Loosely speaking, the state $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ aren't just orthogonal; they're prolifically orthogonal, in a way that can't be un-done by any simple operator. In contrast, if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $ll 1$ millimeter, then we can choose an operator $hat O$ that acts just on the electron (and is therefore relatively simple) to obtain $hat O|arangleapprox |brangle$, thus violating the condition $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$. So in this case, the electron's location has not been effectively measured at all. The states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are orthogonal simply because they differ in the location of the electron itself, but they are not prolifically orthogonal because the effect on the rest of the universe doesn't depend significantly on whether the electron's location was $A$ versus $B$.



                What I'm doing here is describing "decoherence" in a different way than it is usually described. The way I'm describing it here doesn't rely on any factorization of the Hilbert space into the "system of interest" and "everything else." The way I'm describing it here (after quantifying some of my loose statements more carefully) can be applied more generally. It doesn't solve the infamous measurement problem (which has to do with the impossibility of deriving Born's rule within quantum theory), but it does allow us to determine how effectively a given observable has been measured.



                Some quantitative calculations — including quantitative results for the specific example I used here — are described in Tegmark's paper "Apparent wave function collapse caused by scattering" (https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9310032), which is briefly reviewed in https://physics.stackexchange.com/a/442464. Those calculations use the more traditional description of decoherence, but the results are equally applicable to the way I described things here.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$


















                  1












                  $begingroup$


                  Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position.




                  Yes, the influence that an electron exerts on the rest of the universe does depend on the location of the electron, but that's not enough to constitute a measurement of the electron's location. We need to consider the degree to which the electron's influence on the rest of the universe depends on its location.



                  Consider something analogous to but simpler than a double slit experiment: consider an electron in deep space, in a superposition of two different locations $A$ and $B$. Even in deep space, the electron is not alone, because space is filled with cosmic microwave background (CMB) radiation. CMB radiation has a typical wavelength of about $1$ millimeter. When CMB radiation is scattered by an electron, the resulting state of the radiation depends on the electron's location, but the key question is how much it depends on the electron's location. If the locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $gg 1$ millimeter, then the CMB radiation will measure the electron's location very effectively, because an electron in location $A$ will have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. But if locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $ll 1$ millimeter, then an electron in location $A$ will not have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. Sure, the electron has a significant effect on the CMB radiation regardless of its location, but that key is whether the effect differs significantly when the location is $A$ versus $B$. The CMB radiation measures the electron's location, but it does so with limited resolution. Widely-spaced locations will be measured very effectively, but closely-separated locations will not.



                  For this to really make sense, words are not enough. We need to consider the math. So here's a version that includes a smidgen of math.



                  Let $|arangle$ denote the state of the universe (including the electron) that would result if the electron's location were $A$, and let $|brangle$ denote the state of the universe that would result if the electron's location were $B$. If the electron started in some superposition of locations $A$ and $B$, then the resulting state of the universe will be something like $|arangle+|brangle$. Whether or not the electon's location is effectively measured, these two terms will be essentially orthogonal to each other, $langle a|brangleapprox 0$, simply because they differ significantly in the location of the electron itself. So the fact that the final state is $|arangle+|brangle$ with $langle a|brangleapprox 0$ doesn't tell us anything about whether or not the electron's location was actually measured. For that, we need a principle like this:




                  • The electron's location has been effectively measured if and only if the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are such that $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$ for all feasibly-measurable future observables $hat O$. (Quantifying "$approx 0$" requires some care, but I won't go into those details here.)


                  For an operator $hat O$ to be "feasibly measurable", it must be sufficiently simple, which loosely means that it does not require determining too many details over too large a region of space. This is a fuzzy definition, of course, as is the definition of measurement itself, but this fuzziness doesn't cause any problems in practice. (The fact that it doesn't cause any problems in practice is frustrating, because this makes the measurement process itself very difficult to study experimentally!)



                  In the example described above, the suggested condition is satisfied if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $gg 1$ millimeter, because after enough CMB radiation has been scattered by the electron, the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ differ significantly from each other everywhere, and no operator $hat O$ that is simple enough to represent a feasibly-measurable observable can possibly un-do the orthogonality of the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$. Loosely speaking, the state $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ aren't just orthogonal; they're prolifically orthogonal, in a way that can't be un-done by any simple operator. In contrast, if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $ll 1$ millimeter, then we can choose an operator $hat O$ that acts just on the electron (and is therefore relatively simple) to obtain $hat O|arangleapprox |brangle$, thus violating the condition $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$. So in this case, the electron's location has not been effectively measured at all. The states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are orthogonal simply because they differ in the location of the electron itself, but they are not prolifically orthogonal because the effect on the rest of the universe doesn't depend significantly on whether the electron's location was $A$ versus $B$.



                  What I'm doing here is describing "decoherence" in a different way than it is usually described. The way I'm describing it here doesn't rely on any factorization of the Hilbert space into the "system of interest" and "everything else." The way I'm describing it here (after quantifying some of my loose statements more carefully) can be applied more generally. It doesn't solve the infamous measurement problem (which has to do with the impossibility of deriving Born's rule within quantum theory), but it does allow us to determine how effectively a given observable has been measured.



                  Some quantitative calculations — including quantitative results for the specific example I used here — are described in Tegmark's paper "Apparent wave function collapse caused by scattering" (https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9310032), which is briefly reviewed in https://physics.stackexchange.com/a/442464. Those calculations use the more traditional description of decoherence, but the results are equally applicable to the way I described things here.






                  share|cite|improve this answer









                  $endgroup$
















                    1












                    1








                    1





                    $begingroup$


                    Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position.




                    Yes, the influence that an electron exerts on the rest of the universe does depend on the location of the electron, but that's not enough to constitute a measurement of the electron's location. We need to consider the degree to which the electron's influence on the rest of the universe depends on its location.



                    Consider something analogous to but simpler than a double slit experiment: consider an electron in deep space, in a superposition of two different locations $A$ and $B$. Even in deep space, the electron is not alone, because space is filled with cosmic microwave background (CMB) radiation. CMB radiation has a typical wavelength of about $1$ millimeter. When CMB radiation is scattered by an electron, the resulting state of the radiation depends on the electron's location, but the key question is how much it depends on the electron's location. If the locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $gg 1$ millimeter, then the CMB radiation will measure the electron's location very effectively, because an electron in location $A$ will have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. But if locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $ll 1$ millimeter, then an electron in location $A$ will not have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. Sure, the electron has a significant effect on the CMB radiation regardless of its location, but that key is whether the effect differs significantly when the location is $A$ versus $B$. The CMB radiation measures the electron's location, but it does so with limited resolution. Widely-spaced locations will be measured very effectively, but closely-separated locations will not.



                    For this to really make sense, words are not enough. We need to consider the math. So here's a version that includes a smidgen of math.



                    Let $|arangle$ denote the state of the universe (including the electron) that would result if the electron's location were $A$, and let $|brangle$ denote the state of the universe that would result if the electron's location were $B$. If the electron started in some superposition of locations $A$ and $B$, then the resulting state of the universe will be something like $|arangle+|brangle$. Whether or not the electon's location is effectively measured, these two terms will be essentially orthogonal to each other, $langle a|brangleapprox 0$, simply because they differ significantly in the location of the electron itself. So the fact that the final state is $|arangle+|brangle$ with $langle a|brangleapprox 0$ doesn't tell us anything about whether or not the electron's location was actually measured. For that, we need a principle like this:




                    • The electron's location has been effectively measured if and only if the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are such that $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$ for all feasibly-measurable future observables $hat O$. (Quantifying "$approx 0$" requires some care, but I won't go into those details here.)


                    For an operator $hat O$ to be "feasibly measurable", it must be sufficiently simple, which loosely means that it does not require determining too many details over too large a region of space. This is a fuzzy definition, of course, as is the definition of measurement itself, but this fuzziness doesn't cause any problems in practice. (The fact that it doesn't cause any problems in practice is frustrating, because this makes the measurement process itself very difficult to study experimentally!)



                    In the example described above, the suggested condition is satisfied if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $gg 1$ millimeter, because after enough CMB radiation has been scattered by the electron, the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ differ significantly from each other everywhere, and no operator $hat O$ that is simple enough to represent a feasibly-measurable observable can possibly un-do the orthogonality of the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$. Loosely speaking, the state $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ aren't just orthogonal; they're prolifically orthogonal, in a way that can't be un-done by any simple operator. In contrast, if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $ll 1$ millimeter, then we can choose an operator $hat O$ that acts just on the electron (and is therefore relatively simple) to obtain $hat O|arangleapprox |brangle$, thus violating the condition $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$. So in this case, the electron's location has not been effectively measured at all. The states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are orthogonal simply because they differ in the location of the electron itself, but they are not prolifically orthogonal because the effect on the rest of the universe doesn't depend significantly on whether the electron's location was $A$ versus $B$.



                    What I'm doing here is describing "decoherence" in a different way than it is usually described. The way I'm describing it here doesn't rely on any factorization of the Hilbert space into the "system of interest" and "everything else." The way I'm describing it here (after quantifying some of my loose statements more carefully) can be applied more generally. It doesn't solve the infamous measurement problem (which has to do with the impossibility of deriving Born's rule within quantum theory), but it does allow us to determine how effectively a given observable has been measured.



                    Some quantitative calculations — including quantitative results for the specific example I used here — are described in Tegmark's paper "Apparent wave function collapse caused by scattering" (https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9310032), which is briefly reviewed in https://physics.stackexchange.com/a/442464. Those calculations use the more traditional description of decoherence, but the results are equally applicable to the way I described things here.






                    share|cite|improve this answer









                    $endgroup$




                    Seems like the whole universe is receiving information about the electron's position.




                    Yes, the influence that an electron exerts on the rest of the universe does depend on the location of the electron, but that's not enough to constitute a measurement of the electron's location. We need to consider the degree to which the electron's influence on the rest of the universe depends on its location.



                    Consider something analogous to but simpler than a double slit experiment: consider an electron in deep space, in a superposition of two different locations $A$ and $B$. Even in deep space, the electron is not alone, because space is filled with cosmic microwave background (CMB) radiation. CMB radiation has a typical wavelength of about $1$ millimeter. When CMB radiation is scattered by an electron, the resulting state of the radiation depends on the electron's location, but the key question is how much it depends on the electron's location. If the locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $gg 1$ millimeter, then the CMB radiation will measure the electron's location very effectively, because an electron in location $A$ will have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. But if locations $A$ and $B$ differ from each other by $ll 1$ millimeter, then an electron in location $A$ will not have a very different effect on the CMB radiation than an electron in location $B$ would have. Sure, the electron has a significant effect on the CMB radiation regardless of its location, but that key is whether the effect differs significantly when the location is $A$ versus $B$. The CMB radiation measures the electron's location, but it does so with limited resolution. Widely-spaced locations will be measured very effectively, but closely-separated locations will not.



                    For this to really make sense, words are not enough. We need to consider the math. So here's a version that includes a smidgen of math.



                    Let $|arangle$ denote the state of the universe (including the electron) that would result if the electron's location were $A$, and let $|brangle$ denote the state of the universe that would result if the electron's location were $B$. If the electron started in some superposition of locations $A$ and $B$, then the resulting state of the universe will be something like $|arangle+|brangle$. Whether or not the electon's location is effectively measured, these two terms will be essentially orthogonal to each other, $langle a|brangleapprox 0$, simply because they differ significantly in the location of the electron itself. So the fact that the final state is $|arangle+|brangle$ with $langle a|brangleapprox 0$ doesn't tell us anything about whether or not the electron's location was actually measured. For that, we need a principle like this:




                    • The electron's location has been effectively measured if and only if the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are such that $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$ for all feasibly-measurable future observables $hat O$. (Quantifying "$approx 0$" requires some care, but I won't go into those details here.)


                    For an operator $hat O$ to be "feasibly measurable", it must be sufficiently simple, which loosely means that it does not require determining too many details over too large a region of space. This is a fuzzy definition, of course, as is the definition of measurement itself, but this fuzziness doesn't cause any problems in practice. (The fact that it doesn't cause any problems in practice is frustrating, because this makes the measurement process itself very difficult to study experimentally!)



                    In the example described above, the suggested condition is satisfied if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $gg 1$ millimeter, because after enough CMB radiation has been scattered by the electron, the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ differ significantly from each other everywhere, and no operator $hat O$ that is simple enough to represent a feasibly-measurable observable can possibly un-do the orthogonality of the states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$. Loosely speaking, the state $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ aren't just orthogonal; they're prolifically orthogonal, in a way that can't be un-done by any simple operator. In contrast, if locations $A$ and $B$ differ by $ll 1$ millimeter, then we can choose an operator $hat O$ that acts just on the electron (and is therefore relatively simple) to obtain $hat O|arangleapprox |brangle$, thus violating the condition $langle a|hat O|brangleapprox 0$. So in this case, the electron's location has not been effectively measured at all. The states $|arangle$ and $|brangle$ are orthogonal simply because they differ in the location of the electron itself, but they are not prolifically orthogonal because the effect on the rest of the universe doesn't depend significantly on whether the electron's location was $A$ versus $B$.



                    What I'm doing here is describing "decoherence" in a different way than it is usually described. The way I'm describing it here doesn't rely on any factorization of the Hilbert space into the "system of interest" and "everything else." The way I'm describing it here (after quantifying some of my loose statements more carefully) can be applied more generally. It doesn't solve the infamous measurement problem (which has to do with the impossibility of deriving Born's rule within quantum theory), but it does allow us to determine how effectively a given observable has been measured.



                    Some quantitative calculations — including quantitative results for the specific example I used here — are described in Tegmark's paper "Apparent wave function collapse caused by scattering" (https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9310032), which is briefly reviewed in https://physics.stackexchange.com/a/442464. Those calculations use the more traditional description of decoherence, but the results are equally applicable to the way I described things here.







                    share|cite|improve this answer












                    share|cite|improve this answer



                    share|cite|improve this answer










                    answered 1 hour ago









                    Dan YandDan Yand

                    10.5k21538




                    10.5k21538























                        0












                        $begingroup$

                        As long as these interactions are weak and do not distinguish between the two slits, they can be disregarded.






                        share|cite|improve this answer









                        $endgroup$


















                          0












                          $begingroup$

                          As long as these interactions are weak and do not distinguish between the two slits, they can be disregarded.






                          share|cite|improve this answer









                          $endgroup$
















                            0












                            0








                            0





                            $begingroup$

                            As long as these interactions are weak and do not distinguish between the two slits, they can be disregarded.






                            share|cite|improve this answer









                            $endgroup$



                            As long as these interactions are weak and do not distinguish between the two slits, they can be disregarded.







                            share|cite|improve this answer












                            share|cite|improve this answer



                            share|cite|improve this answer










                            answered 10 hours ago









                            my2ctsmy2cts

                            5,2782618




                            5,2782618






















                                FunkyLoiso is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










                                draft saved

                                draft discarded


















                                FunkyLoiso is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.













                                FunkyLoiso is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.












                                FunkyLoiso is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
















                                Thanks for contributing an answer to Physics Stack Exchange!


                                • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                                But avoid



                                • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                                • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                                Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                                To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                                draft saved


                                draft discarded














                                StackExchange.ready(
                                function () {
                                StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphysics.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f460855%2fhow-come-particles-are-not-constantly-measured-by-the-whole-universe%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                                }
                                );

                                Post as a guest















                                Required, but never shown





















































                                Required, but never shown














                                Required, but never shown












                                Required, but never shown







                                Required, but never shown

































                                Required, but never shown














                                Required, but never shown












                                Required, but never shown







                                Required, but never shown







                                Popular posts from this blog

                                If I really need a card on my start hand, how many mulligans make sense? [duplicate]

                                Alcedinidae

                                Can an atomic nucleus contain both particles and antiparticles? [duplicate]